Making Sense - Sam Harris - September 09, 2022


#295 — Philosophy and the Good Life


Episode Stats

Length

44 minutes

Words per Minute

172.36334

Word Count

7,618

Sentence Count

6

Misogynist Sentences

1

Hate Speech Sentences

3


Summary

Kieran Setia is a professor of philosophy at the University of mit and the author of Midlife: A Philosopher Guide, a guide to the ongoing project of living a good life. As well as Life is Hard: How Philosophy Can Help Us Find Our Way, his writing has also appeared in the Los Angeles Review of Books, The Times Literary Supplement, The London Review of books, the London Literary Supplement and The New York Times, and the Yale Review. In this conversation, we talk about the relevance of philosophy to the project of making people better human beings, and how philosophy can help us find our way in the world. We discuss the existence of objective moral truths, the claim that the self is an illusion, the power of reframing FOMO toward the future, the asymmetry between pain and pleasure, and other topics. I really enjoyed this conversation and hope you find it useful. To access full episodes of the Making Sense podcast, you ll need to become a subscriber.Become a supporter of the podcast by becoming a Misericordian, a M.I.P. member (becoming a member is a good thing to do so, and you ll get access to all kinds of excellent resources, including the latest episodes of Making Sense Podcasts, including our newest podcast, The Making Sense. If you enjoy what we're doing here, please consider becoming a member! To find a list of our sponsors, go to bit.ly/OurAdvertisers/Becoming a patron of the making sense Podcast, where you can get 10% off the price of a new episode of the show, plus a free copy of our newest book, "Making Sense: How to Live a Good Life: A Guide to the Good Life?" Subscribe to our newest issue of The Making sense Podcast by clicking here to get 20% off your first month of the book, The Good Life Guide to a copy of the new edition of the next issue of Making sense: Life Is Hard: A Platonic Guide? Learn more about our new book "Life is Hard, a philosophical guide to living a Better Life: How To Live Better, a Guide to Life Is It Hard? by Kieran S. Setia, a new book by the philosopher and philosopher, coming out soon, out soon? Join us at Making Sense: A philosophical guide by the author, Kristian Setia? Want to buy a copy?


Transcript

00:00:00.000 welcome to the making sense podcast this is sam harris just a note to say that if you're hearing
00:00:12.520 this you are not currently on our subscriber feed and will only be hearing the first part
00:00:16.900 of this conversation in order to access full episodes of the making sense podcast you'll
00:00:21.800 need to subscribe at sam harris.org there you'll find our private rss feed to add to your favorite
00:00:27.020 podcatcher along with other subscriber only content we don't run ads on the podcast and
00:00:32.500 therefore it's made possible entirely through the support of our subscribers so if you enjoy
00:00:36.540 what we're doing here please consider becoming one today i'm speaking with kieran setia kieran is a
00:00:50.860 professor of philosophy at mit and he's the author of midlife a philosophical guide as well as life is
00:00:58.980 hard how philosophy can help us find our way his writing has also appeared in the los angeles review
00:01:04.900 of books the times literary supplement the london review of books the new york times aeon and the
00:01:12.420 yale review and in this conversation we talk about the relevance of philosophy to the ongoing project
00:01:19.420 of living a good life we discuss the existence of objective moral truths being happy versus living
00:01:27.040 well a response to grief meditation as a remedy for psychological suffering how to understand the
00:01:34.640 claim that the self is an illusion the difference between telic and atelic activities the power of
00:01:41.900 reframing fomo bias toward the future regret the asymmetry between pain and pleasure and other topics
00:01:52.260 i really enjoyed this conversation i hope you find it useful and now i bring you kieran setia
00:01:59.520 i am here with kieran setia kieran thanks for joining me thanks so much for having me so um we have
00:02:13.300 many shared interests i loved your book midlife a philosophical guide and you have a new book which
00:02:20.240 i just have a pdf of it's coming out soon and i've just glanced at that but i think we can
00:02:26.720 sort of merge the themes in both your books over the course of this conversation but before we jump
00:02:32.620 in there maybe you can summarize your background academically and intellectually what kinds of
00:02:39.640 problems and concerns have you focused on well i'm a philosophy professor i teach at mit and my work
00:02:46.520 on the sort of academic side has been about questions about the nature of human agency
00:02:50.380 human knowledge and broadly speaking in ethics sort of anything related to the problems of
00:02:56.720 how we should live and then over the last i guess five seven years i've been doing more outward
00:03:03.920 facing work that we'll talk about midlife and how it came out of my own experience but i've been
00:03:09.740 trying to think about how the tools of academic philosophy could be applied to the kinds of problems about how
00:03:18.260 to live that my friends and i seem to be facing and going through some of which philosophers talk about
00:03:24.260 many of which they tend not to to spend so much time on so the midlife crisis is one and then in the new
00:03:29.880 book life is hard loneliness and grief and failure and the kind of challenges that we confront when we're
00:03:36.280 living lives that are inevitably imperfect yeah i've i've often marveled and i'm not alone in this
00:03:43.240 in the marveling at um the broken connection between philosophy and the project of living well
00:03:52.400 that used to be the whole point of philosophy to come up with some vision of life and the world
00:03:59.120 that made securing as durable a possible a form of well-being you know we'll talk about just you
00:04:09.100 know what can be hoped for there and it was just intrinsic to the project of you know literally
00:04:15.380 you know loving wisdom and that's the very concept of philosophy and then it became this far more
00:04:21.860 abstract and arcane discipline where it seemed to want to emulate mathematics and science more and it
00:04:31.480 became a you know following wittgenstein a really just a kind of language game which viewed
00:04:39.020 everything in terms of you know the parsing of concepts and i just feel like we lost our purchase
00:04:45.860 on something important there i don't know if you share that that feeling i mean i think there's a lot
00:04:50.000 of truth to that you know philosophers are often embarrassed by the idea of self-help but in a way
00:04:57.640 when you sort of think of the long trajectory of the history of philosophical ethics the idea that
00:05:02.620 thinking about how to live should make your life better should enable you to live better
00:05:06.160 is a very kind of attractive plausible one and that makes the line between moral philosophy
00:05:13.180 ethics and what would nowadays be thought of as self-help pretty blurry and they really only start
00:05:18.580 to diverge sort of in the 18th century you get philosophers who want to sort of pull apart the
00:05:23.940 project of understanding morality or ethics from the project of sort of making people virtuous making
00:05:30.200 people better and philosophy a lot of what philosophers do now is relevant i mean it's
00:05:36.340 closely relevant to practical questions about how to live and some of that people know about through
00:05:41.140 things like effective altruism so bits that are bits of philosophy that are directed to the question
00:05:45.480 what are your obligations to other people but the relevance of philosophy is much broader than that
00:05:50.460 but it's very much concealed by the way in which philosophy is sort of now formulated as and structured
00:05:56.920 institutionally as an academic discipline and i kind of wanted to reconnect those two and bring them
00:06:02.500 back into conversation yeah well that's what i loved about your book midlife and what i know i will love
00:06:08.920 about life is hard and in midlife you remind us all of three questions that kant asked which are really
00:06:18.380 foundational to the whole project of philosophy at least the first two i guess i have some concern about the
00:06:24.760 the third but the first the questions are what can i know what should i do and what may i hope
00:06:32.160 and uh i think you and i both have some caveats to add to the concept of hope but um you know what can
00:06:39.520 i know that really is is all of epistemology and what should i do it really crystallizes moral philosophy
00:06:47.740 and ethics and you know ultimately even meta-ethics in what sense can things matter and how do we solve
00:06:58.700 this this navigation problem of life in my mind morality is pretty much always a question of what
00:07:05.200 we should do next given the space of all possible experience in which we're navigating and there's a deeper
00:07:12.800 question about how any claims we might make about what we should do relate to claims about what is
00:07:20.040 true and what what is knowable how do you think about just the grounding of of moral truth in a larger
00:07:28.600 set of truth claims i mean the central problems of of meta-ethics do you spend much time thinking about
00:07:34.900 that yeah so i i do and i i tend to be sort of sympathetic to the idea that there there are
00:07:41.860 objective ethical truths i mean there's various kinds of lines that get drawn here that i think
00:07:47.020 drawing which sort of i think played a role in the divorce between say philosophical ethics and self-help
00:07:53.620 like drawing a line between morality as concerned with our obligations to others and then ethics as
00:08:00.180 concerned with sort of how we should live more broadly those two i think are sort of interconnected
00:08:04.800 in ways that make them hard to separate and similarly you sort of mentioned meta-ethics and
00:08:09.380 there was a kind of period in mid-20th century moral philosophy where a lot of philosophers wanted to
00:08:14.160 to do something say something about ethics sort of meta-ethics in a way that didn't really engage
00:08:20.380 with the question how to live they wanted to separate the question of the nature of morality
00:08:23.800 from practical questions about what what the ethical standards were and i think that there's a kind of
00:08:30.460 tendency in recent moral philosophy ethics that i think is right to blur those lines and to suggest
00:08:36.060 that we can't really draw those distinctions and i think that that sort of blurring of lines also
00:08:41.380 applies to the kinds of questions about objectivity that you're raising so on the one hand you know
00:08:46.600 there's a lot of moral disagreement a lot of disagreement in ethics and when we try to engage
00:08:51.660 in ethical arguments we often sort of come to loggerheads with other people and it seems like
00:08:56.460 there's a kind of question about how we could know the answer or whether there are really objective
00:09:00.200 answers and that can seem like a challenge to the idea of objective ethical truth on the other hand
00:09:06.240 when you think about questions about what we know or what the standards of scientific rationality are
00:09:11.560 one lesson of thinking about sort of determined conspiracy theorists or science deniers is that if you insist
00:09:19.220 on rejecting any premise that could be used to dislodge your your view you can maintain consistency
00:09:27.760 at the cost of an increasingly warped but internally coherent perspective on how the world is scientifically
00:09:36.300 and so i think these problems about you know how do you actually persuade people and how does our failure
00:09:42.800 to persuade people what what significance does that have for the idea of objective knowledge and objective
00:09:47.460 truth are much broader than ethics and i think in both cases the right response is to say something
00:09:52.200 like well you know dialectical efficacy like being able to actually persuade people is one thing but the
00:09:59.160 fact that you can't persuade someone who's a conspiracy theorist or a committed flat earther and will say
00:10:05.300 anything it takes to to avoid internal inconsistency that shouldn't make us think that that's a legitimate
00:10:11.340 view it's still an unjustified response to the evidence even if it can be made strictly logically
00:10:17.180 compatible with the evidence and in the same way in ethics i think we shouldn't be dissuaded from the
00:10:23.120 idea that there really are objective knowable answers to questions about how we should live
00:10:28.000 by the fact that we find ourselves sometimes faced with intractable ethical disagreements that's not to
00:10:35.100 say that there aren't differences between the case of science and ethics i think a kind of pluralism
00:10:39.200 about the variety of different good ways to live is appropriate in ethics and maybe that kind of pluralism
00:10:45.020 doesn't have the same role to play in our thinking about science but i think that the sort of questions
00:10:50.920 of you know how do we know what do i know and what should i do are sort of deeply entangled and i don't
00:10:57.700 think that there's a sort of it's very hard to explain why one should be skeptical about objective
00:11:03.700 ethical truth in a way that doesn't just eat up the whole idea of objective rationality altogether
00:11:09.440 well you just seem to have argued for the thesis of my book the moral landscape in a wonderfully concise
00:11:16.060 way i don't know if you've seen that book i do know the book yes yeah yeah i mean i obviously i agree
00:11:22.100 with everything you just said you you made a point which i make there but you sort of made it from the
00:11:26.280 other side which i find um pretty illuminating i mean the complaint i've often lodged is that scientists
00:11:35.200 and philosophers do something different they do something with the diversity of opinion on moral
00:11:42.900 topics that they don't do with diversity of opinion on any other topic which is to say they conclude
00:11:48.920 from the mere existence of disagreement that there is no ground truth to be known right so the fact that
00:11:55.740 someone can show up at your morality conference and say well i happen to like the morality of the
00:12:00.960 taliban what are you guys going to do with that basically the conference just dissolves at that
00:12:06.120 point because people begin to say well clearly you know it's all just made up it's all cultural
00:12:11.620 convention there's no there can be no objective or universal claims about good and evil or right and
00:12:17.960 wrong because we've got the taliban over there doing you know cutting people's heads off at halftime
00:12:23.380 of their soccer games and that's and they tell us that's how they want to live what are we going to do
00:12:27.580 but my point has always been if you ask the taliban about physics or epidemiology you're not going to
00:12:34.080 get a lot of good sense either right the fact that they have opinions on those topics is never read
00:12:40.140 by experts in those fields as evidence of anything other than their ignorance right and so the idea that
00:12:46.900 you can find a an island of people who are living in some starkly awful way by our lights shouldn't
00:12:55.360 convince you you know on its face that they have an equal claim to having thought through the problem
00:13:03.320 of you know what is good what is right you know what is the moral structure you know if there is one
00:13:09.900 in human affairs or in the larger affairs of conscious creatures and that you know they that their language
00:13:17.620 game needs to be taken seriously the way the language games of our experts do and so it's just the fact
00:13:24.620 that we just sort of throw out the rule book of what it would mean to just try to push the conversation
00:13:31.020 further into persuasion and to also recognize that in every other sphere of of life there are people
00:13:38.260 who are unpersuadable because there are people who you know as you say they're they're committed to some
00:13:43.340 form of dogmatism that's causing them to just change the rules of conversation on their side so as to be
00:13:49.600 immune to any stream of evidence or argument that would destabilize their worldview we don't read into
00:13:55.680 that when you know when we're talking to young earth creationists we just you know we don't view
00:14:00.620 that as a real challenge to our geology or astronomy or paleontology or anything else and yet that's not
00:14:07.400 the not the feeling you get when talking about questions of right and wrong and good and evil among
00:14:12.980 academics generally.
00:14:14.240 I think that's exactly right I mean there's this phenomenon or kind of idea that comes out of 20th
00:14:19.860 century philosophy of science mid-20th century philosophy of science of the underdetermination
00:14:24.500 of theory by data the idea is if you're willing to adjust your auxiliary hypotheses you can always
00:14:31.480 avoid accepting any theory that seems to be supported by the data by reinterpreting how exactly the
00:14:37.520 observations were related to theory or how they were gathered or disputing the the reliability of such and
00:14:44.120 such instrument and that the standard response not the only response in philosophy of science is to
00:14:48.480 say well yeah there's more to scientific rationality than just bare consistency with the evidence like
00:14:55.920 just not contradicting the evidence is not all there is to coming up with the best most justified most
00:15:03.620 illuminating most explanatory best theories and I think it's a puzzle to which there were kind of
00:15:09.820 interesting historical answers why we don't take the same view in ethics of saying well yeah someone
00:15:16.360 can hold a consistent internally coherent but abhorrent moral view an abhorrent view in ethics that doesn't
00:15:23.540 mean that there's no fact of the matter or that there's no justification what it means is well there's
00:15:29.060 more to ethical rationality sort of thinking well about ethics than just not contradicting yourself and
00:15:35.440 put that way it really shouldn't be that surprising that mere consistency is not all there is to you
00:15:42.740 know ethical virtue in one's thinking about ethics itself so I think you know the degree of disagreement
00:15:49.820 historically and socially is maybe different and that maybe invites people to to suppose that there's
00:15:56.060 some dramatic contrast between ethics and science but it's really a difference of degree and you know
00:16:01.920 as conspiracy theorists become more prevalent the differences of degree may start to diminish yeah
00:16:08.320 yeah well the uh the problem of persuading people about ordinary facts I mean just you journalistic
00:16:15.740 facts at this point has become fairly excruciating so that the the idea that it remains difficult
00:16:22.500 to persuade people about divergent moral facts that's somehow no longer surprising we can't even agree
00:16:31.520 about what should be on the front page of a newspaper at this point but uh that concern notwithstanding
00:16:37.580 let's plunge in I think a good place to start is the distinction you make between being happy and
00:16:45.280 living well how do you think about those two concepts yes I think this is this is sort of a kind of
00:16:51.240 distinction that gets drawn in in various ways in in philosophy but also in ordinary life so I think it one way
00:16:59.080 to sort of see the contrast between being happy and living well and sort of asking yourself you know
00:17:04.040 what is the object of self-help and is the goal to be happy or to live well is to think about
00:17:09.040 either there are sort of abstract wild philosophical thought experiments like people plugged into
00:17:15.680 simulation machines in which nothing they're experiencing is real they're actually completely
00:17:20.440 alone everyone they seem to be interacting with is fake nothing that they think they're doing or
00:17:24.460 almost nothing are they really doing many people have the thought well that is not a life I want
00:17:29.280 for people I love that's not that's not sort of a good human life that's barely living at all
00:17:33.800 but of course the person who's in that situation of of deception and illusion could feel incredibly
00:17:41.200 happy they feel great they're in terms if we think of happiness as the kind of subjective state of
00:17:46.160 mood or satisfaction they have it and what that suggests is yeah there's more to living well than
00:17:52.480 happiness it's not that we should not care about happiness or strive to be unhappy but that's not
00:17:57.680 really the goal of life the goal is to live well and that sometimes involves unhappiness and the
00:18:04.560 unhappiness that comes with confronting reality so there's also as well as these wild thought
00:18:08.800 experiments I think it's something that people are very vividly confronted with when they think about
00:18:12.520 grief where the idea that that the pain of grief and the unhappiness of grief and the sadness of
00:18:18.740 grief among the other complex array of emotions that grief involves the idea that somehow well it
00:18:25.460 would just be better if we could get rid of that that just doesn't seem right this the relationship
00:18:29.920 between the pain and suffering of grief and living well is much more complicated than that and I think
00:18:36.480 that's a more general phenomenon that the relationship between negative emotions negative feelings and
00:18:42.480 living well doesn't always make your life worse in fact it's very important to living well to
00:18:48.700 recognize when things are bad to sort of to live in the world as it is not the world as you wish it
00:18:57.060 would be and so I think it's very important to sort of frame the philosophical project of ethics and the
00:19:03.620 self-help project in terms of living well primarily and happiness only secondarily and one thing that does is to make clear that the
00:19:12.480 boundaries between oneself and others are much more porous so when you start to think about living well
00:19:18.660 part of living well is living as you should and the question of how should I live well it doesn't
00:19:24.540 immediately tell you how you should care about other people but invites you to ask well if I'm going to
00:19:29.220 live as I should how should I integrate the rights and needs of other people into my life and if you were just
00:19:36.460 thinking about happiness it might seem like well any connection between happiness and caring about other people
00:19:42.240 is contingent and often caring about other people makes you vulnerable to unhappiness but once you
00:19:47.240 think no the goal is not just to feel happy it's to actually live a good life you start to sort of break
00:19:53.300 down the boundaries between what we might think of as self-interest and what we might think of as
00:19:57.820 morality and I think that's a useful way of sort of reframing what the project of self-help might look
00:20:03.600 like if it was inspired by a kind of philosophical approach to ethics.
00:20:08.620 Hmm yeah there's a lot in what you just said I mean there's so many intersecting questions and
00:20:14.860 problems to sort out I mean so one point you made about grief which I find really interesting and I
00:20:21.840 think it's a certain point it is going to be a an actionable use case for all of us that will pose some
00:20:28.820 interesting psychological and ethical challenges and the way I've put it elsewhere I think I might have
00:20:35.380 been in in the moral landscape it certainly was in some things I said while talking about that book I just
00:20:40.580 I asked people to imagine what it's going to be like when we develop if we develop as seems pretty likely
00:20:47.980 a real cure for grief and bereavement right so let's just say we have a grief pill that you could take
00:20:56.240 and you know within an hour you will no longer feel sad about that thing you've been completely brokenhearted
00:21:03.080 over whether it's the death of a loved one or the the loss of a relationship or pick your poison there
00:21:08.740 if we had a cure for grief the question immediately arises you know whether to take it ever and if to
00:21:17.420 take it how long do you wait right and clearly it seems like some kind of awful norm violation
00:21:26.160 and even a break of trust with the person we ostensibly love if while their body is still warm
00:21:35.180 we pop the pill and you know 45 minutes later we're out in an arcade playing video games
00:21:43.600 to date myself with an anachronistic reference but it's like it's the idea that the love of your life
00:21:52.040 dies and that you would want to take a pill which nullified your bereavement immediately that somehow
00:21:59.660 seems incompatible with love itself of course you some you know real experience of grief seems
00:22:09.000 appropriate and desirable but then the question is is there any point where grief itself becomes
00:22:15.480 maladaptive and no longer a sign of just how important that person was to you but also a sign of
00:22:23.200 a failure of resilience and a failure to thrive and a failure to live in precisely the way your your loved
00:22:30.360 one would want you to live after they're gone right so like at what point at some point you could imagine
00:22:35.960 a grief pill really could be a a necessary intervention for someone whose life has just
00:22:42.440 unraveled under the pressure of bereavement so i get there's a half a dozen other things that
00:22:47.520 occurred to me as you were talking but maybe we could take that case do you have any thoughts about
00:22:52.440 sure i mean it's a fascinating thought experiment i mean in fact there's already a kind of natural
00:22:58.180 experiment that that prompts anxieties of the kind you're describing so that the empirical work on
00:23:04.700 grief suggests that most people tend to be quite resilient even in the face of loved ones that they
00:23:10.540 were deeply attached to and often within you know six months their lives are almost back to normal
00:23:16.240 and that actually occasions a lot of discomfort and anxiety the sort of sense that there's something
00:23:22.800 something has gone wrong with one's attachment given how rapidly it's possible to recover so even
00:23:29.380 without the grief pill we sort of have a kind of emotional immune system that restores us to
00:23:34.700 equilibrium much faster than many of us expect and in fact much faster than many of us are comfortable
00:23:39.400 with and when you try to think through why that is i mean part of the answer seems leads to another
00:23:43.760 puzzle you raised about how long so part of the answer seems to be well when you think what am i
00:23:48.860 grieving for well there's the loss of the relationship there's how bad it was for the person who died the life
00:23:54.780 that they could have had but there's also just a kind of recognition of the sheer loss of of life
00:24:00.180 grief and grief is is a kind of rational response to that like in the same way as we have reasons for
00:24:07.180 other emotions like anger is a response response to a sort of perceived insult or fear is a response to
00:24:14.400 danger or threat grief seems to be a kind of the reason for it is a certain kind of loss and the puzzle is
00:24:22.380 well actually that that's what starts to answer the question why we shouldn't take the pill the thought is
00:24:28.660 if we didn't grieve in response to the loss of someone we love we wouldn't be taking in reality
00:24:34.700 this goes back to the contrast between being happy and living well we want to take in reality
00:24:38.660 and in reality we should feel grief we should respond in a way that acknowledges the the terribleness
00:24:46.280 of that loss but then the puzzle is hold on if the reason for grief is just that my loved one is dead
00:24:54.140 that's not going to change i mean the reason that just stays the same and it stays the same forever
00:24:59.780 so now we face the question the puzzle is less why should we grieve or whether we should grieve but
00:25:05.900 how can we ever justifiably stop grieving and there's a real puzzle there i mean it you know
00:25:12.400 when you try to describe how the situation has changed later you think to yourself it's true they
00:25:18.660 died a while ago and i've grieved for a while but those things all seem irrelevant to the scale of
00:25:24.200 the loss like those things don't make it any don't sort of diminish their loss in having died so how
00:25:30.180 can they make it rational to stop grieving and i think this is this is kind of a puzzle i talk about
00:25:34.600 in the chapter on grief in life is hard i think this is where really what's happening is that our
00:25:40.180 emotions respond to reasons and this is a case where if we just look at the object of the emotion
00:25:46.440 and try to proportion our emotional response to changes in it we'll find that there's just a
00:25:52.860 kind of indeterminacy we don't know it does there's no there's nothing in the object of grief that tells
00:25:58.300 you how long to grieve for and this is i think one reason why rituals of grieving sort of practices of
00:26:05.680 mourning which are not rationally mandated they take various cultural forms are so important because
00:26:12.300 what they do is allow you to sort of grab onto something to sort of guide and shape the process
00:26:18.180 of grieving in a way that enables you to at least you know in practice get through this sense of the
00:26:25.640 arbitrariness of grieving for a certain length or or others and and you know often what they have is is
00:26:32.640 sort of distinctive temporal shapes so like you sit shiva for seven days or you know in ancient roman
00:26:39.100 customs there were sort of you know guidelines for how many months you should mourn for a child or a
00:26:45.160 wife or you know what they do is precisely try to to regulate something that if we just look at the
00:26:52.180 object of grief would seem unregulable and i think that is a kind of a deep sort of feature of the nature
00:26:58.560 of grief and the way in which it responds to to to loss so yeah i think we can sort of answer the
00:27:04.800 question what would we lose if we took the grief pill by saying well we wouldn't be responding to
00:27:08.720 reality the way we should and then we face this problem okay how how can we ever justifiably stop
00:27:15.400 recognizing that loss for what it is and we sort of rely on what are to some extent conventional
00:27:22.040 arbitrary social practices to help us do that yeah that's all very interesting and useful although
00:27:28.800 there's there's a mystery on the other side of the continuum here which is that one could ask
00:27:34.520 how one ever justifiably starts grieving in the sense that and this has a direct connection to
00:27:41.980 you know meditation and mindfulness and just the nature of consciousness that you know i know you
00:27:47.740 know that's an interest of mine because i mean just for instance you take my present circumstance
00:27:52.200 right you know i'm recording this conversation with you i'm alone which is to say that no one i love
00:27:59.000 is present in my studio now they're never going to be more absent for me than they are now right my wife
00:28:07.500 and kids or i you know i know them to still exist i have no reason to be bereaved but the truth is
00:28:14.480 i also know that i am totally fine in their absence right so the question is how do i ever become
00:28:23.640 someone who is not fine in their absence not only not fine but how does their absence become
00:28:31.680 synonymous with really the ruination of my well-being for whatever half-life that suffering
00:28:41.340 has for me you know in the case of you know everyone i love dying and you know it seems like a
00:28:48.560 perhaps a callous question or at least a bizarre one but in terms of the mechanics of psychological
00:28:56.300 suffering it's a very real one because the way you the way we suffer is to think about the reasons
00:29:05.200 we have to suffer in this case it is a kind of abstraction and the thought i will never see her
00:29:11.340 again meets out its punishment to you in the act of identifying with it and that's why meditation
00:29:18.380 promises to be a truly generic remedy for psychological suffering because it's you know
00:29:24.640 it's in being able to break the spell of thought that one can recognize that consciousness is if only
00:29:33.040 for that next moment free of the implications of thought and i actually i know from reading midlife
00:29:40.100 you have some concerns about the you know what's considered the center of the bullseye here that the
00:29:44.740 illusoriness of the self and and perhaps we'll we'll get there i'd love to speak with you about
00:29:48.600 that but you're the conundrum you posed about how it ever becomes reasonable to stop grieving
00:29:54.320 i do think is actually mirrored on the other side by this property of the mind how is it that it becomes
00:30:01.380 so reasonable to start grieving when in this moment i know that and you know and any listener must know
00:30:10.240 that it's totally possible to not only endure the next moment of being of solitude you can thrive
00:30:19.280 in this next moment of solitude and and how does that fundamentally change ever that's really that
00:30:27.340 is very interesting and i think it relates to it to a distinction i want to draw between different
00:30:32.980 objects of grief and sort of the plurality of things that grief attaches to so a distinction i think
00:30:38.300 is useful is between relational grief or grief about the end of a relationship and grief for the
00:30:45.540 sake of the one who's died and they come apart so you know when you have a terrible breakup and the
00:30:51.240 person hasn't died nevertheless there's something like grief the the the sort of devastation of
00:30:56.160 rejection and loss of a relationship and then when someone you love dies there's both you both have
00:31:01.600 this the phenomenon that the relationship is is now i think not really ended but it changed it's
00:31:06.940 ruptured and changed in a dramatic way and then you have i think also grief for their sake and i think
00:31:12.380 part of what you're pointing to is that if we focus on relational grief the kind of relationship you think
00:31:17.600 well insofar as my relationship i was capable of being happy in my relationship with someone in their
00:31:25.080 absence all i have to do to get through grief is more of that and so yeah why why shouldn't i just
00:31:33.220 sort of stay in in the the mode of of being fine in their absence and i think there's an that is a
00:31:39.180 very interesting puzzle but i think it deals with one side of grief the sort of relational side the
00:31:43.780 relationship focus part about you know i'll never see them again i'll never interact with them again
00:31:48.320 and i think there is also a dimension of grief that is not in that way it's not that relational
00:31:54.420 grief is self-regarding but it is it involves you as one of the two you know sides of the relationship
00:32:00.280 i think there's also grief that is just not relational it's just about the death of someone
00:32:04.400 else and there i think the issue of how your you could survive their absence doesn't seem to offer
00:32:12.560 consolation the thought is it's just a fact that they are dead and the appropriate sort of emotional
00:32:18.660 response to the enormity of that fact is to grieve to to to go to begin this sort of complicated
00:32:26.020 difficult emotional process and i think i think that kind of sort of outward looking for the sake
00:32:32.500 of them grief it's not clear to me that it's it's subject to the same therapy you just gave i think the
00:32:39.020 therapy for that would have to be something much more radical which would point us towards the
00:32:43.460 non-existence of the self and sort of more more radical buddhist ideas where the thought would be
00:32:48.800 you know if we could fully take in that we don't really exist and no one we're attached to really
00:32:54.940 exists in the way we think they do if that was really true and we could really take it in
00:32:58.500 then the thought might be well the kind of loss that attachment would bring this sort of outward
00:33:05.160 looking loss where the value of something irreplaceable is just gone and you're you're sort of
00:33:10.040 devastated by that it would be sort of answered by sort of denying that we really existed in the kind
00:33:17.900 of way that would make us fit objects of that kind of attachment i mean there are many puzzles about
00:33:22.520 this we could talk about and one puzzle for me is that it's never been clear to me really why
00:33:26.660 the sort of revelation of no self isn't like sort of discovering that everyone you know and love
00:33:34.060 including you is already dead i mean it's itself a kind of devastating discovery and in fact there's
00:33:40.500 this idea of mindfulness meditation as a kind of therapy that is stress reducing the sort of
00:33:48.140 empirical literature on that that's sort of divorced from its the kind of insights that buddhist mindfulness
00:33:53.880 meditation is supposed to bring us to but there are sort of aspects of the buddhist tradition in
00:33:58.300 which meditation of this kind is not really stress reduction it's a form of stress induction like the
00:34:04.280 process is supposed to be one of confronting something very very difficult like the non-existence of
00:34:11.000 yourself and those you love is a kind of devastating thing to confront what's true is that once you've confronted it
00:34:18.140 you come out on the other side and you've as it were already pre-processed the grief you're through
00:34:23.260 as it were through to the other side of grief and that sort of makes sense to me what what i feel like
00:34:28.660 might be having it both ways is a kind of picture of mindfulness meditation on which both the process
00:34:34.940 the process itself involves stress reduction and the outcome involves a kind of equanimity i feel like
00:34:41.920 that is the thing that it i find it harder to make make sense of okay yeah so maybe we'll deal with it now
00:34:49.380 yeah i think there's some confusion about what is meant by no self in buddhism or really in any contemplative
00:34:57.200 tradition and certainly any of the the indian contemplative traditions that you know spread east and and north so
00:35:04.640 this is now encompassing all variants of buddhism including vajrayana and also indian teachings like
00:35:12.380 advaita vedanta and not to say that the adherents of all those traditions think they're all teaching
00:35:18.400 precisely the same thing but at their core i think there is a the same insight at the end of the day
00:35:25.080 that is being described and entangled with you know various forms of religious belief and dogmatism and
00:35:33.680 it's more or less mingled with with helpful or harmful concepts to varying degrees and in these
00:35:39.160 various traditions but the core insight is that well first we can mean many different things by the
00:35:46.720 term self and not all of them are illusory so it's not the claim that people are illusions or that you
00:35:55.660 can't say anything coherent about the biographical or psychological continuity of a person right i mean it's
00:36:03.120 not mysterious that i wake up today as me and not as you in a different house in a different life
00:36:09.000 etc i mean that's not that's not a puzzle that anyone is trying to solve and i do think they're
00:36:14.380 very interesting puzzles around identity you know a la derek parfit but the real insight here and the
00:36:22.520 illusion that is cut through and again it's cut through not merely conceptually but experientially
00:36:28.820 is the apparent default condition of feeling like there's a subject in the center of experience
00:36:39.360 most people don't merely feel identical to experience they feel like they're having an experience they
00:36:48.280 feel like they're appropriating their experience from some point very likely in their heads that is
00:36:54.560 just the witness the thinker of thoughts the guider of attention the the willer of will the free will
00:37:00.240 the guy in the boat who has free will who can decide what to think and do next that's the default
00:37:07.380 state for more or less everybody as far as i can tell and it's a peculiar point of view as commonplace
00:37:15.160 as it is it doesn't make a lot of sense it certainly doesn't make biological sense it's not the same thing
00:37:20.340 as feeling identical to your body because people again don't feel identical to their bodies they feel
00:37:26.580 like they're subjects who have bodies to a large degree i mean they feel this is kind of a cartesian
00:37:32.460 dualism here that is intuitive for people and this is i think my friend paul bloom has said that people
00:37:40.400 are common sense dualists and i think that's true and that does link up with many beliefs about
00:37:46.760 the divorceability of mind from brain and you know you know the immortality of the soul and all the
00:37:52.280 rest i mean it seems somehow intuitive that your mind must be something other than what the brain is
00:37:56.380 doing and it you know it may in fact be you know i'm not actually somewhat agnostic as to how
00:38:01.640 consciousness is arising in this universe and it's you know i take the hard problem of consciousness
00:38:06.940 seriously that's a separate question but as a matter of experience there's this feeling
00:38:11.800 that i'm a subject behind my face in some cases certainly under conditions of being embarrassed or
00:38:20.640 you're being suddenly made the object of other people's attention i can almost feel like i'm
00:38:25.600 wearing my face as a mask right i mean you think of what it's like to feel acutely self-conscious and
00:38:30.500 to be blushing say in front of somebody you know you're at odds with your own face and so where the hell
00:38:37.640 are you in this situation you're the subject who's thinking and so it's that point of view who we
00:38:44.980 represent so now this is sort of the totality of conscious experience here we represent the world
00:38:50.020 so we have the deliverances of our senses we see and hear and smell and taste and touch and so there's
00:38:54.820 the full set of our our perceptions and there's there's more to it than that there's proprioception
00:39:00.800 and everything else you can be consciously aware of your body in space so there's the world and you
00:39:06.320 then you represent your body in the world but again from the point of view of the subject
00:39:10.380 your body is a kind of object in the world it's out there to some degree and you're in you're in it
00:39:17.760 and you so then there's this final representation of being a subject internal to the body that is
00:39:24.880 directing attention thinking thoughts willing its will and vulnerable to the the warp and woof of of
00:39:31.920 of life so it's that final representation of the subject that is the illusion and to put this in
00:39:40.080 neurological terms you know this is let's just say for the sake of argument that all of this is just
00:39:45.080 you know neurophysiological events in the brain and delivering these these representations it is
00:39:51.200 plausible or at least should be plausible that any one of these processes can be interrupted right so you
00:39:57.420 can cease to faithfully or coherently represent a world right you can suddenly you know go blind you
00:40:03.560 know you can suddenly not be able to name living things but still be able to name tools you can
00:40:10.800 suddenly not be able to perceive motion or location you know those things break apart all kinds of
00:40:16.920 things can be disrupted for worse certainly but what these contemplative traditions have recognized is that
00:40:23.900 certain things can be disrupted or brought to a halt for the better right and the thing that
00:40:32.100 that really does really can interrupt the usual cascade of of mediocrity and suffering psychologically
00:40:39.600 speaking is this representation of self as subject in the middle of experience it is a kind of
00:40:46.680 again i realize i've been bloviating for quite some time here giving you a lot and there's much more to
00:40:52.000 say on this but the you can represent the world and you can represent your body in the world and you
00:40:58.440 can cease to represent a subject internal to the body or cease to i should say construct a subject
00:41:05.280 internal to the body and what remains in that case is a sense that the mind is much vaster than it was a
00:41:16.380 moment ago because it's no longer confined to the sense that there's this central thinker of thoughts
00:41:23.640 there's the recognition that thoughts simply arise all by themselves just the way sounds do right
00:41:29.620 there's no no one is authoring your thoughts you certainly aren't in fact the sense that you are is yet
00:41:35.560 is what it feels like to be identified with this next spontaneously arising thought so you lose the sense
00:41:42.440 that that you're on the edge of your life you're on the edge of the world sort of looking over your own
00:41:48.320 shoulder appropriating experience and what you can feel you know very vividly again this is not a new way of
00:41:55.940 thinking about yourself in the world this is a a ceasing to identify with thought what you can feel is a real
00:42:04.520 unity and again there there's fine print here and whether we want to talk about this as unity or as
00:42:10.160 emptiness my preferred formulation here is non-duality a non-duality of subject and object such that
00:42:17.740 there really is just experience right again i'm not making any metaphysical claims about how this relates
00:42:23.300 to matter or the universe but as a matter of experience you can feel identical to experience itself
00:42:29.820 right you're not having an experience you're not on the edge of the river watching things go by you
00:42:35.320 are the river and that solves a very very wide class of problems psychologically speaking with respect
00:42:43.160 to suffering so it does land in a surprising kind of equanimity and even eudaimonia that may seem
00:42:52.740 counterintuitive in the midst of the cacophony of ordinary life but it's there to be found but again it's
00:42:59.340 not it's not the negation of personhood it's not it doesn't introduce all kinds of conundrums about
00:43:05.360 how am i me and not you it's just a recognition that as a matter of experience there is just experience
00:43:14.360 and then the feeling that there's an experiencer is yet more experience right so there's like you if you
00:43:19.460 drop back there is just everything in its own place anyway so i've given it gave you a lot there but
00:43:27.040 that's my attempt to perform an exorcism on the concept of no self that you seem to be working
00:43:32.240 with well i i mean i think there's something deeply right about the line of thought you're
00:43:37.520 you're pushing i what i find hard to get in in fields i still struggle with this sort of
00:43:43.780 if you'd like to continue listening to this conversation you'll need to subscribe at samharris.org
00:43:49.980 once you do you'll get access to all full-length episodes of the making sense podcast along with
00:43:55.100 other subscriber only content including bonus episodes and amas and the conversations i've
00:44:00.680 been having on the waking up app the making sense podcast is ad free and relies entirely on
00:44:06.000 listener support and you can subscribe now at samharris.org
00:44:09.840 you