#382 — The Eye of Nature
Episode Stats
Words per Minute
166.6611
Summary
In this episode of the Making Sense Podcast, Richard Dawkins joins us to talk about his new book, The Genetic Book of the Dead, and why he thinks genes are immortal. He also discusses the problem of free speech in the UK, which has reached surprising proportions, as well as the rise of political Islam and anti-Semitism. And then, we close with some reflections on our friend Dan Dennett's book, "The God of Small Things." This episode was produced and edited by Sam Harris. To find a list of our sponsors and show-related promo codes, go to gimlet.fm/OurAdvertisers. We don t run ads on the podcast, and therefore, therefore, are made possible entirely through the support of our subscribers.If you enjoy what we're doing here, please consider becoming a supporter of the podcast by becoming one of our members. You'll get access to our scholarship program, where we offer free accounts to anyone who can't afford a full-time college education. There's no ad-free version of the Podcast without the usual fees, which means you'll get twice the quality and value you get when you sign up. If you're not a member yet, you can become a member for as little as $1/month, and get 10% off for the rest of the month, plus a 20% discount when you upgrade your membership gets you access to the full-fat version of The Making Sense Program, for as much as 40% off the course, for up to $99 a year, plus an additional $150 a year! We're giving you get a free copy of our latest edition of our newest edition of Making Sense, The Testaments! We'll be giving you a copy of The Bookshop edition of The Testimonials, The Good Mythology and a freebie of The Good News: The Test, The Bad News Journal, and a discount on the Test, and an extra $50 off the Test! Make sure to check out the Test by clicking the Good News Club, and receive a discount code: Good News, Good News Only, Good Luck! Good Luck, Good Success, Good Life, Good Problems, Good Things, Good Grief, Good Relationships, Good Thoughts, and Good Things! by Bad News, Bad Relationships by Good News by Good Readings by Goodie Goodie, and Much More! by Goody Goodie and Goodie!
Transcript
00:00:00.000
Welcome to the Making Sense Podcast. This is Sam Harris. Just a note to say that if
00:00:11.640
you're hearing this, you're not currently on our subscriber feed, and we'll only be
00:00:15.580
hearing the first part of this conversation. In order to access full episodes of the Making
00:00:19.840
Sense Podcast, you'll need to subscribe at samharris.org. There you'll also find our
00:00:24.960
scholarship program, where we offer free accounts to anyone who can't afford one. We don't run
00:00:29.340
ads on the podcast, and therefore it's made possible entirely through the support of our
00:00:33.120
subscribers. So if you enjoy what we're doing here, please consider becoming one.
00:00:45.280
Well, today's guest needs no introduction. Often one says that and then just gives the introduction
00:00:51.560
anyway, but no, Richard Dawkins actually needs no introduction on this podcast, except to say that
00:00:58.460
he has a new book, which is titled The Genetic Book of the Dead, which we speak about in the
00:01:04.420
first part of the podcast, where we talk about the genome as a kind of palimpsest, what scientists
00:01:12.380
of the future may be able to do with our genetic information, genotypes and phenotypes, embryology
00:01:18.720
and epigenetics, why the Lamarckian theory of acquired characteristics just couldn't be true,
00:01:24.240
how environmental selection pressure actually works, why evolution is so hard to think about,
00:01:30.620
human dependence on material culture, the future of genetic enhancement of human beings,
00:01:37.620
viral DNA, symbiotic bacteria, AI and the future of intellectual life, the prospect of resurrecting
00:01:46.300
extinct species. And then we pivot to politics. We talk about the problem of free speech in the UK,
00:01:52.480
which has reached surprising proportions, as well as the problem of political Islam and
00:01:59.500
anti-Semitism. And then we close with some reflections on our friend Dan Dennett. And now I
00:02:06.520
bring you the one and only Richard Dawkins. I am here with Richard Dawkins. Richard, thanks for joining
00:02:17.680
me again. Great pleasure, Sam. Thank you. So you have a new book, which I'm sorry to say I have not
00:02:24.660
read in its entirety because I can only spend so much time reading a PDF that gets sent to me. I do
00:02:30.460
not have the physical book yet, but I have read enough to declare that it is fascinating and that
00:02:36.020
people should go out and buy it. So we'll talk a little bit about it, but there are a few other
00:02:40.600
things I want to talk to you about. Yes. But first, how are you and what is your life like
00:02:46.380
these days? I think you and I had lunch about, I don't know, a couple of months ago, but... Yes,
00:02:50.480
we did. Are you traveling or what's happening? Yes, well, I'm doing a tour of North America at
00:02:56.160
the moment and then it carries on in Britain and Europe. And I've said it's my final tour and
00:03:02.140
it's partly to promote the book. In fact, I suppose it's mostly different to promote the book.
00:03:06.280
And how long are you on the road for? Five weeks in North America and then
00:03:12.220
indefinitely, well, a couple of weeks in Britain and Europe.
00:03:16.960
Mm-hmm. Nice. Well, needless to say, I hope it's not your final tour, but... Or I hope that
00:03:21.880
doesn't say anything about your longevity, but... Yeah, I hope so too. Yeah. My last tour might
00:03:27.200
have been my final tour too, so you never know. So let's touch on the book. The title is the...
00:03:34.800
The Genetic Book of the Dead. The Genetic Book of the Dead, yeah. And it's a reference which
00:03:39.080
you disavow early on. It produces an echo which you disavow early on. That's right. It's an echo
00:03:45.160
to the Egyptian books of the dead. And the Tibetan, I would point out, there's also a Tibetan book.
00:03:49.600
Yes, and the Tibetan. It's just a kind of poetic allusion, really. It doesn't really discuss
00:03:55.200
those books. There's a kind of vague relevance in that I talk about genes as being immortal in the
00:04:02.960
sense that they go on for generation after generation, whereas bodies are cast aside and
00:04:06.780
die. And so the genes are a kind of set of instructions to the body as to how to not proceed
00:04:14.800
to the afterlife, as it would be in the Egyptian books of the dead, but how to hand the genes
00:04:19.640
on to the afterlife, which is the next generation and the next and the next and so on.
00:04:24.240
Right. So if we were going to take the analogy literally, and you also draw an analogy, a similar
00:04:31.480
analogy to a palimpsest, which you might describe what that is, but these are both analogies to
00:04:38.100
books. We'll tell our listeners or remind them not to be too pedantic what a palimpsest is.
00:04:43.560
Okay. A palimpsest is a piece of writing which is partially or wholly erased so that you can write
00:04:51.400
again on the same medium. So in the days when there wasn't an abundant ability of paper,
00:04:57.620
people would reuse the same parchment and they would erase what was already there and then write
00:05:04.840
over it. And I had a dear friend, Bill Hamilton, a very distinguished evolutionist who wrote postcards
00:05:12.380
where he would economize by writing in blue horizontally, and then he would turn it to a
00:05:17.880
right angle and write in red, carrying on the message. And you could read it by deciphering
00:05:22.700
the coding red, blue, and which way it was pointing.
00:05:27.600
You provide an example in the book, which I must say I found difficult to read. I mean,
00:05:31.080
that seemed like a provocation to one's friends to be sending them letters of that kind.
00:05:35.920
Actually, I did manage to decipher, I think it's the red, I forget which color it was.
00:05:40.420
It's really rather dramatic. It's something to do with somebody getting his bike
00:05:43.540
rammed or something like that. I didn't really read too much of it. But the point is that the
00:05:52.340
genetic book of the dead is a description in the genes and in the body of an animal of all its
00:06:00.300
ancestral worlds, all the worlds in which its ancestors lived, because natural selection has
00:06:05.140
shaped it, has shaped the genes to survive in those worlds. But of course, since its ancestors lived in
00:06:11.500
so many different worlds, old, very old, slightly old, and so on, until relatively recent, and then
00:06:16.780
now, it is a palimpsest of writings from all these different ages where they've been partially erased
00:06:23.460
and then written over and then partially erased and written over again.
00:06:27.360
Yeah, I want to go over that statement again, just because it's beautiful and I don't want people to
00:06:31.560
miss the import of it. So to come at it from the other side, if we could read the genetic book
00:06:42.340
In the case of any of a human or any mammal, we would read old writings about the sea when our
00:06:49.440
ancestors before the Devonian era lived in the sea. Then we would read writings about the emergence onto
00:06:56.220
the land. We would read writings about subsequent history and so on. In the case of primates going up
00:07:01.800
into the trees, some animals went back into the water, which is remarkable, having sort of got all
00:07:06.920
tooled up to come onto the land to then go back into the water. And I've got a subchapter where
00:07:11.800
turtles and tortoises actually came back for the third time. So they came out of the water onto the
00:07:18.020
land, back to the water. So there were land tortoises in the Triassic era, back to the water as sea
00:07:26.100
turtles, where some of them remain, and then back to the land again as modern land tortoises. So that's
00:07:36.780
And what do you imagine future biologists will be able to do with the genome?
00:07:43.800
Okay, I have a sort of recurrent fantasy about a zoologist of the future, a scientist of the future.
00:07:49.740
I make her female and I call her SOF, a scientist of the future. And I believe that scientists of the
00:07:57.680
future will be able to read the book which is the animal and its genes and piece together the entire
00:08:04.680
palimpsest of its ancestral history. It's something we can't do at the moment. And parts of the book
00:08:13.620
are about the little preliminary fumbling steps, nursery slopes steps, which we can make towards that
00:08:21.440
end. Given an unspecified genome, how close are we to being able to predict the phenotype of the
00:08:31.100
animal? Not very close. And that, of course, would be a big problem for the genetic book of the dead.
00:08:37.580
And much of the book actually is not about genes at all. It's about using the phenotype of an animal
00:08:42.640
to reconstruct the book, which is its set of ancestral histories. SOF, in the future, will be able to do it
00:08:50.080
with the genes. And we can't really do that now. There is no decoding process whereby you can get
00:08:56.960
a genotype and say what the ancestral worlds of this animal were.
00:09:02.580
I think, Richard, we should probably remind people of just, we should define our terms here. What's
00:09:07.240
the difference between a genotype and a phenotype?
00:09:09.480
Well, a genotype is the set of genes in the animal. And the phenotype is what the genes manifest
00:09:14.540
themselves as. So the phenotype is the body, its behavior, everything that we actually see of the
00:09:19.440
animal. So what I asked you, given the genome, the series of base pairs, the code that's in the
00:09:26.980
nucleus of almost every cell in an animal's body, could we predict what that animal would look like?
00:09:39.860
Not really. What you can do is to say exactly what proteins would be programmed by that animal's
00:09:48.600
genome. But the problem then is that the animal itself is produced by the processes of embryonic
00:09:55.440
development, which are masterminded by genes via the proteins. But the actual process itself is such
00:10:03.500
that unless you know a lot about the animal already, you can't really tell. If you're given
00:10:08.500
a wholly new animal that's been found in the seas, sorry, a whole new genome that has been found,
00:10:14.540
and you have no idea what kind of animal it is, then you couldn't reconstruct it. But if you could
00:10:18.320
say, ah, yes, well, this evidently is a species of kangaroo, because it looks like existing kangaroos,
00:10:25.460
then you're away, and then you can do something with it. But if you know nothing about it, the
00:10:32.900
only way to really find out what that animal would develop as would be to put the genome
00:10:37.860
into a, well, into a female, or the species concerned, and let it develop.
00:10:43.460
Yeah. You actually have a very seditious sentence at some point early in the book, which I think
00:10:50.780
you say something like, forgive me for putting dangerous words into your mouth, but they were
00:10:58.080
dangerous on the page. You say something like the best machine for translating a genotype into a
00:11:04.280
phenotype that we know of is a woman, or something like that.
00:11:07.360
Yes, that's right. That's right, yes. I could have said any female.
00:11:11.420
Yes, right. Well, perhaps we'll return to that combustible topic.
00:11:15.900
So, what is meant by the word epigenetics, and where does that concept come into play here?
00:11:23.240
Epigenetics is, I think, a much misused word. It's really just a word for embryology. The thing
00:11:29.600
is that every cell in your body, every cell in our bodies, has the same genome, the same diploid
00:11:35.700
set of genes, and yet the cells are all different. So liver cells are different from kidney cells,
00:11:40.960
different from muscle cells, and so on. And the reason is epigenetics. The reason is that some
00:11:45.880
genes are turned on in liver cells, and different genes are turned on in kidney cells, different
00:11:50.580
genes are turned on in nerve cells, and so on. That's epigenetics. Now, there has very recently
00:11:56.800
been a suggestion that some of these turnings on of genes can get passed on to the next generation.
00:12:04.800
And this has been shown for a few cases. And the word epigenetics has come to be dubbed onto that
00:12:13.580
process of passing on to the next generation. And that's unfortunate, because it's become a kind of
00:12:20.520
vogue word of great popularity, suggesting a kind of major revolution. Some people have even thought
00:12:26.020
that it looks like Lamarckian inheritance of acquired characteristics, which it really isn't.
00:12:30.760
Well, let's just circle on that concept for a second again, just to capture everybody's
00:12:35.740
understanding. What was the Lamarckian thesis, and to what degree does the heritability of some
00:12:47.460
Okay. Lamarck lived before Darwin, and he had really the only other theory for how evolution could
00:12:55.200
work. And it was a bit mystical. He had this idea that animals kind of strive to change their way of
00:13:03.460
life, and they stretch their... The giraffe by striving to reach higher and higher leaves.
00:13:08.960
That's right. It stretches its neck. And then he had two main principles, the principle of use and
00:13:14.620
disuse. The more you use a bit of your body, the bigger it gets. So the more you use certain muscles,
00:13:20.480
the bigger they get. That's why you go to training. And as the giraffe stretches its neck,
00:13:25.440
everything about the neck stretches. So that's the principle of use and disuse.
00:13:29.520
Then he had the principle of inheritance of acquired characteristics. An animal inherits
00:13:35.060
from its parents those changes which occur during the parent's own lifetime. So the giraffe's
00:13:41.840
babies inherit a slightly longer neck because the parents stretch their necks.
00:13:47.300
If you exercise your muscles with weight lifting, then your children are born with slightly bigger
00:13:54.240
muscles. That would be the principle of inheritance of acquired characteristics plus use and disuse.
00:13:59.440
And it's all false. It doesn't happen. I mean, use and disuse happens, but acquired characteristics
00:14:04.500
are not inherited. Now, the modern vogue for what they call epigenetics, where certain genes get
00:14:11.080
turned on, which they do during embryology, those genes that get turned on, if that turning on gets
00:14:16.680
passed on to the next generation, then that is a kind of inheritance of an acquired characteristic.
00:14:23.220
But it's very different from the giraffe's neck. It doesn't have the same adaptive potential. It
00:14:28.660
doesn't have the potential to pass on to the next generation the improved capacity to survive,
00:14:35.480
which the principle of use and disuse would. That's one reason why it's not Lamarckian.
00:14:41.300
Another reason is that it doesn't go on to subsequent generations. It works only for the
00:14:45.040
next generation, not for the indefinite future, which it would have to in order to be evolutionarily
00:14:50.780
Yeah, so let's clarify that point. So let's give an example of what we think actually could
00:14:56.240
be transmitted from generation to generation by way of epigenetics. I mean, what is, forgive me,
00:15:03.080
I'm not close to this literature at all, but I believe I've consumed somewhere the idea that,
00:15:07.720
you know, various environmental stresses, let's say the subjection of one population to a near
00:15:15.440
genocide. I mean, some, you know, generational trauma meted out to people.
00:15:20.280
Right, starvation could do something to the epigenetic settings of the people.
00:15:25.220
Yeah, it could change the physiology of the children in some way.
00:15:30.020
But it would not go forward to the grandchildren or the great-grandchildren or the great-great-grandchildren.
00:15:35.180
Because it doesn't change the germline of the children.
00:15:37.980
Exactly. It doesn't change the germline. It changes which members of the germline got switched
00:15:43.460
on. But I don't think it's interesting because it's at least not evolutionary. I mean, it's quite
00:15:48.360
interesting from some points of view. It's not evolutionarily interesting because it doesn't
00:15:51.680
go on to the indefinite future. It would have to go on to the indefinite future to be evolutionarily
00:15:56.720
interesting. By the way, I mean, I think it's quite important, quite interesting to think about
00:16:03.120
why the Lamarckian theory doesn't work. I mean, even if it were true that acquired characteristics
00:16:09.620
were inherited, even if the giraffe's neck was inherited, it would not be good enough,
00:16:15.940
it would not be a powerful enough theory to explain almost everything about evolution. If you
00:16:20.720
take something like an eye, where eyes get progressively better at focusing, more clarity,
00:16:28.640
more detail, more precision, that doesn't happen by just use and disuse. It's not the case that the
00:16:35.860
more you use an eye, the more acute the vision becomes. On Darwin's principle, Darwin actually used
00:16:43.260
the phrase, nature is daily and hourly scrutinizing every detail. That's one of the main themes of the
00:16:48.780
genetic book of the dead that daily and hourly, any tiny detail inside the animal buried, however,
00:16:54.640
deeply within the animal, which improves the animal's chance of surviving, then that survives
00:16:59.180
and that can go on to the next generation and the next and the next and the next.
00:17:03.040
Actually, perhaps you can discuss an example of that. I know you go through many in the book,
00:17:07.720
but the one that I recall is with camouflage with respect to, you know, lizards and moths.
00:17:13.540
Okay. Yes. So the thing I want you to illustrate is the point you're making about the daily and
00:17:19.920
hourly scrutiny of the environment. Yes. That's a lovely phrase of Darwin, by the way. The first
00:17:25.580
picture in the book, I think, is this lizard. It lives in the desert and all over its back,
00:17:32.140
it's got pictures of sand and stones and pebbles. It looks as though it's got a desert painted on its
00:17:38.620
back. And this is camouflage, of course. And there are many other examples, beautiful examples of
00:17:44.080
camouflage where in every case you can say that the animals, or rather the environment of the
00:17:48.940
ancestors is painted on the animal's back. Well, those are very spectacular examples.
00:17:55.460
But the thesis of the genetic book of the dead is that it's more than just skin deep. Exactly the same
00:18:01.200
attention to detail must pervade every tiny scrap of detail all the way through the animal. It's not
00:18:08.320
just the skin. It's more than skin deep. It goes right through the animal. The daily and hourly
00:18:13.820
scrutinizing produces the picture of a desert on the lizard's back, but it also produces every little
00:18:20.300
tiny mote of detail inside the animal, which assists its survival. Anything that assists survival
00:18:27.080
and passing on of genes is fair game for natural selection. That just doesn't, the principle of
00:18:33.060
use and disuse and inheritance of acquired characteristics can't do that because it doesn't
00:18:38.760
have this sort of power to adjust to every single detail that Darwinism does. Because if it assists
00:18:46.280
survival, it gets through to the next generation and therefore into the future.
00:18:50.280
But to explain how this could be so incremental, I mean, so you have a moth that looks now exactly
00:18:58.300
like the bark of the tree that is its habitual stopping point, but obviously no moth could have
00:19:06.080
evolved fully in one generation to look that way. So how is each increment justified and solidified
00:19:16.300
by this, by the attention of the daily and hourly attention of the environment?
00:19:22.320
You have to start from an ancestor which looked hardly anything like the bark of a tree. Or think
00:19:29.960
of a stick caterpillar, which is another beautiful example where a modern stick caterpillar looks
00:19:35.900
uncannily like a stick. It's got little leaf bud scars and everything looks like a stick. Well,
00:19:41.620
originally the ancestor would hardly have looked like a stick at all. It would have just been a
00:19:45.980
vaguely long shaped thing, which most caterpillars are. So why, how did the, you're asking the
00:19:52.120
question, how did the incremental process proceed step by step by step to go from a very crude ancestral
00:19:58.760
resemblance to a stick right up to a modern extreme perfection of resemblance to a stick? And the answer,
00:20:06.900
I think, is that the final perfecting stages were provided by full frontal vision by a predator in a good
00:20:15.520
light with full attention playing on the object. Whereas the early stages might have been predators who were
00:20:23.560
just sort of, might have caught sight of this thing out of the corner of their eye while flashing past, or maybe
00:20:29.760
in a poor light. Well, under those bad, or from a long distance away. So from a long distance away in a poor
00:20:36.280
light and out of the corner of your eye, even a very crude resemblance to a stick will escape the
00:20:42.940
attention, escape the notice of the predator. And that provides the selection pressure to slightly
00:20:50.900
So just the slightest change in the probability of being, of not surviving there is because now
00:20:58.580
you're dealing with just the, all those occasions where you were barely in the field of view of the
00:21:04.700
predator. Just that slight modification is enough to encourage that, that differential success of that
00:21:11.760
adaptation. Exactly. Exactly. And then, and then the gradient goes steadily upwards because you've got
00:21:16.880
a whole gradient, a whole spectrum of improved seeing conditions. I mean, if the very poor resemblance
00:21:24.340
is good enough to fool a predator at a hundred yards away, then at 90 yards away, it's got to be
00:21:30.260
slightly better in order to, and there are going to be predators that are seeing caterpillars at all
00:21:35.960
those distances. And under poor seeing conditions, the selection pressure produces the, the first stages
00:21:42.880
in the gradient of improvement to the, to the mimicry. And then the last stages are provided by
00:21:49.260
predators that are looking straight at the caterpillar in a good light, and they're still fooled by it
00:21:55.040
because the resemblance is so perfect. Yeah. It's really just an amazingly beautiful process to think
00:22:02.020
about in, in that regard. Yes. Why is it so hard to understand this intuitively? I mean, or perhaps
00:22:11.060
another way of asking the question is, what do you think the barriers are for, um, just a, just a
00:22:17.740
widespread intuitive understanding of the reality of evolution? I suppose partly it's that the time
00:22:26.500
scale involved is so huge and we're not equipped to deal with millions of years, let alone hundreds
00:22:32.180
of millions of years. That's one thing. Isn't the time scale sometimes surprisingly compressed?
00:22:38.680
It's short. It is indeed. That's right. And, and, and that's perfectly true. And, and in the case of
00:22:43.360
the evolution of, of mimicry, it could, it could be quite fast.
00:22:48.160
But sort of either present their own impediment, because if it's too short, it just seems like
00:22:53.140
there's not enough time to have accomplished that miracle. And if it's too long, it's very hard
00:23:01.140
Well, maybe there is a sweet spot. Maybe, but it, but it'll, it'll vary in, in the different
00:23:06.680
One hundred thousand years. That's the sweet spot. Yeah.
00:23:08.680
Well, well, it depends. I mean, it, it might be for some, for some cases in, in, and it
00:23:13.960
might be a million years in others. Um, but it probably is surprisingly fast. Another thing
00:23:19.080
I think is that people don't realize that a very, very slight advantage is enough to exert
00:23:26.420
evolutionary change. So when, when you think about the, you know, can it really be a good,
00:23:32.300
can it really matter whether you've got, say, eyebrows? I have no idea why we have eyebrows,
00:23:37.840
but suppose it's to stop sweat trickling into our eyes. I don't think it is, but just,
00:23:46.800
Okay. Um, well, you might say, oh, well, what does, why does it matter if sweat trickles
00:23:52.080
into your eyes? I mean, does that really affect survival? Well, it might, because you,
00:23:56.640
you might not see the, the saber tooth approaching quite so soon if your eyes are all gummed up with
00:24:02.740
sweat. Especially if there's sunblock mingled in with the sweat.
00:24:06.120
Especially, yes. And the point is that it, that because we're dealing with genes and the statistical
00:24:12.340
frequencies of genes as they change in frequency over generations, any gene that tends to make
00:24:18.560
eyebrows stop the sweat trickling into your, into your eyes. It's not just the one occasion. It's all
00:24:24.300
those thousands of occasions of different individuals where the same gene has its beneficial
00:24:29.660
effect, not only the same individuals at the same time, but through, through different times. So
00:24:35.680
statistically, a gene can have a very small beneficial effect, but that beneficial effect
00:24:41.500
is kind of multiplied up over all the different individuals that it influences over a larger stretch
00:24:46.720
of time where it does its influencing. And because of that, those genes, which are good at helping
00:24:53.380
individuals to survive, are the ones that we see, the ones that actually come through the generations.
00:24:58.960
So even a very slight advantage, like stopping sweat trickling into your eyes, is enough to do the
00:25:04.320
trick, even though that's counterintuitive. And you ask the question, why is it intuitively so hard
00:25:09.440
to understand? I think that's another, another reason.
00:25:11.580
What do you make of the fact that human beings seem so imperfectly selected to survive without
00:25:22.660
material culture, right? I mean, so like, actually, our David Deutsch, who I know, you know, at least
00:25:29.160
by reputation, if not personally, over there in Oxford, you know, very smart man. He's, he's made
00:25:35.280
the point that, um, the earth already is essentially a spaceship for us, right? So like, if you just
00:25:42.660
leave him out exposed, even to an Oxford night, you know, uh, without the benefit of shelter or
00:25:48.960
clothing or fire, or, you know, he, he's, you know, for at least many nights of the year, he's likely to
00:25:55.040
die of hypothermia, right? So it's like, we're, we're just not, we're, we're these naked apes that are
00:26:00.100
not great at survival apart from being in tribal bands who have produced a, a modicum of material
00:26:08.160
culture that, and, and an ability to pass on that culture to subsequent generations. But in and of
00:26:15.180
themselves, you know, each, you know, representative of the species devoid of culture, you know, put on a
00:26:21.600
desert island is liable to die in, you know, over the course of 72 hours or a week because of just
00:26:27.940
being fundamentally unable to survive when slammed up against raw nature. What do you make of the
00:26:34.900
difference between human beings and basically everything else we see in the living world?
00:26:41.480
I suppose if you were to go back to our time when we lived for such a long time in Africa,
00:26:46.780
in, in the savannah, we would have been a lot better at surviving as individuals then. Even then we would
00:26:53.100
have needed culture, but nothing like so much as we do today. I mean, now we have supermarkets,
00:26:58.560
we get our food prepared for us. We don't have to go and get it. We don't have to go and find it or
00:27:03.240
hunt it or kill it or gather it. We just go into a shop and buy it. And we are mollycoddled by
00:27:09.120
electricity and central heating and all that kind of thing. If you were to take not a, a modern
00:27:16.060
American and, or Englishman and put him out on, on, on the, expose him to the, to the elements,
00:27:21.820
you might die. But if you were to do the same with a Kung Sam from the Kalahari Desert,
00:27:27.460
they're a lot better at surviving. Yeah. Or Australian Aboriginal. At least in the Kalahari
00:27:31.660
Desert, yeah. Yes. Or Australian, a native Australian in, in, in the Australian outback.
00:27:36.920
They do pretty well. And I think we've co-evolved culturally and genetically. And when we've
00:27:43.500
gradually emancipated ourselves, I mean, our genes have, have gradually moved us on into a world in
00:27:52.320
which we, because we are surrounded by culture and culture has been, has been gradually evolving
00:27:56.620
at the same time, well, much faster than we have become dependent upon the culture, which has been
00:28:05.120
evolving at this very rapid rate. Things like wearing clothes, things like taming fire and going
00:28:11.920
onto central heating and cooperative living such that we have farmers who grow food for us so we
00:28:18.740
don't have to grow it ourselves, et cetera. I think it's not that difficult to understand how it's
00:28:23.360
happened, this co-evolution with, with culture and technology. What are you expecting us to do
00:28:30.680
with our increasing power to, to actually engineer changes within our own genomes? If you had a time
00:28:38.900
machine and you could glimpse what we're up to on that front 50 years from now or a hundred years
00:28:45.160
from now, what, what would you expect? We've been changing the genomes of domestic animals and
00:28:51.640
plants for thousands of years, very, really, very radically. And so the sort of domestic animals that
00:28:57.800
we keep like cattle and horses and pigs, chickens, and pets like dogs are incredibly different from
00:29:04.940
their wild ancestors. And that's been achieved not by manipulation of the genes directly, but by
00:29:10.820
artificial selection. So if you think that a Pekingese and a Chihuahua are actually genetically wolves
00:29:16.900
that have been modified by differential selection by humans, you've now, you're now asking the question
00:29:23.720
about the other part of the Darwinian equation, which is mutation. We've shown we've, we can modify
00:29:29.840
animals by selection. We've never done that with humans and the Nazis tried and thank goodness
00:29:35.080
they didn't succeed. But I mean, you could have bred, I mean, one, one could imagine it in thousands
00:29:40.440
of years time. If totalitarian regimes started selecting humans, the way we've selected dogs
00:29:45.760
and cabbages, you could produce all sorts of monstrous humans, analogous to producing Chihuahuas from,
00:29:52.600
from wolves. And yeah, but obviously you could do it much more quickly.
00:29:56.960
Yes, it's much quicker. And, and, but, but you couldn't, you, you, you don't know what you're
00:30:00.880
doing. Coming back to your earlier question, you, we don't actually know very much about how to do
00:30:05.920
that. If, if you wanted to produce a, not just as a human, say, say you want to produce an animal,
00:30:12.340
take one that hasn't been domesticated, like say a hedgehog. You want to produce a hedgehog,
00:30:16.820
which could do the high jump and jump impressively high fences. In principle, you could do it, you
00:30:23.520
could do it by selective breeding. It would take a while, but, but there's no reason why you couldn't
00:30:28.340
gradually improve the jumping ability of a hedgehog until it could jump a foot and then two feet and
00:30:33.140
so on. Just the way you be bred dogs to change from wolves into, into Pomeranians and Spaniels.
00:30:40.180
But to go into the genome of a hedgehog and say, let's change the genes to make it into a high
00:30:45.340
jumper. That's in principle possible, but would take a lot more knowledge than we have at present
00:30:51.620
how to, how to do that. The same with humans. But I would think that if we just keep making
00:30:57.500
progress, we will eventually have the, the understanding of, of the relevant genomes and
00:31:04.060
the technology by which to intrude into our own genomes. And we are essentially, we already have
00:31:09.760
CRISPR and presumably that's only going to get better and better and better understood in terms of
00:31:15.320
the implications of making any change. At a certain point, I mean, we, we, we already see
00:31:20.720
an appetite for body modification and general strangeness in, among humans, right? We see people
00:31:28.600
who tattoo their entire body bodies. We see bodybuilders who develop their, their musculature
00:31:34.780
to the, the absolute maximum capacity, you know, with the aid of a pharmacology that compromises
00:31:40.320
their physical health, right? And this also happens among athletes. So there's clearly an appetite
00:31:45.480
for extreme performance and extreme aesthetics that, you know, completely divorced from performance
00:31:54.360
of any kind. You know, even degraded performance, you know, that, that allows for extreme aesthetics.
00:32:00.340
There's an appetite for that. So once we get the ability to, let's say, modify the tendons and
00:32:10.780
ligaments and muscles in such a way as to make, make a person, you know, analogously strong to,
00:32:19.060
you know, to a gorilla or a chimpanzee, do you have any doubt that people are going to start doing
00:32:25.480
that the moment that technology becomes remotely democratized?
00:32:29.440
You know, if you're asking me about whether I have doubt to whether people would take advantage
00:32:33.120
of the opportunity, I mean, I don't have any doubt. Whereas people do the most extraordinary
00:32:36.740
things. Yes, I think that they would. I sort of, I sometimes say, say, well, we, we haven't changed
00:32:41.500
humans by selection the way we've changed dogs. So why would we change them by genetic manipulation?
00:32:47.560
But of course there is an important difference, which is that selection is something that takes
00:32:50.720
many generations. Yeah. And it could be done by totalitarian regime.
00:32:55.400
This is the question of what you could do to yourself as a consenting adult.
00:32:58.800
What you could do to yourself is another matter, because, because that could be much quicker.
00:33:02.280
And yes, I suppose that's true because bodybuilders already, I mean, some, if you look at some of the
00:33:07.660
pictures of extreme bodybuilders, they are, well, I don't, I was going to say, I was going to say
00:33:12.340
grotesque, perhaps that's not unkind, but, but it shows what can be done by various sorts of
00:33:17.900
manipulation and genetic manipulation could be even more powerful than that. So yes, I could
00:33:23.440
imagine that whether it would just be physical, I mean, maybe you could even produce musical geniuses,
00:33:28.740
make it, make another Mozart or another Bach by this means is a tantalizing thought.
00:33:34.020
I guess I'm, I spend very little time thinking about this, you know, the far future or even the,
00:33:39.340
the near far future with respect to this. But I spend much more time thinking about the
00:33:44.120
implications of artificial intelligence with respect to this kind of time horizon. But
00:33:48.220
when you think of genetic engineering, it's very, it's very hard for me to imagine what would
00:33:55.120
prevent us from going some significant distance down this path, right? I mean, I, I, obviously we,
00:34:03.060
there are concerns about synthetic biology and the engineered pandemics and, and all of that. And,
00:34:08.440
and also there are ethical concerns of the sort that you, you reference with, with respect to
00:34:13.360
eugenics and, you know, totalitarian control of populations. But when you just imagine the
00:34:19.260
technology becoming more and more available to the, to the individual user and in the way that,
00:34:25.400
you know, by analogy, in the way that drugs illegal and otherwise are, are legal and otherwise are,
00:34:30.720
are available to people now, you know, the anabolic steroids being the example we're, we're using
00:34:36.440
with respect to bodybuilding. I just, it's very hard to imagine us avoid culturally,
00:34:42.340
you know, perfectly collaborating to avoid extreme outcomes on a global level. I mean,
00:34:48.400
I just don't see how we avoid it. Yeah. Yeah. I quite agree.
00:34:53.260
Okay. Well, is there anything else in the book that you want to draw listeners attention to in
00:34:58.780
terms of your purpose in writing it or what you was, what was most interesting to you and
00:35:03.640
researching it? There is a sort of sting in the tail, I suppose, in the, in the last chapter,
00:35:07.700
which you won't have got to yet, where I make the suggestion that we should regard all our own
00:35:13.940
genes, what we call our own genes as symbiotic viruses, a gigantic colony of symbiotic viruses.
00:35:24.500
And that's not as radical as it sounds. It, it, it, it does, it doesn't mean that a whole lot of
00:35:29.720
independent viruses sort of like the flu virus and COVID virus and so on came together in us.
00:35:35.740
It doesn't mean that it's rather that I make a distinction when looking at parasites or looking
00:35:41.160
at symbionts like, like viruses or bacteria between those that get to a new victim by passing through
00:35:48.980
the gametes, passing through the sperms and eggs of the present victim. So imagine a bacterium or a,
00:35:55.260
or a virus whose method of getting from human to human is by eggs or sperms. Then if you think about
00:36:05.780
what they want of their, of the body in which they sit, what they want is exactly the same as what the
00:36:12.280
body's own genes want. They want the animal to reproduce. They want it to survive, therefore,
00:36:18.140
in order to reproduce. They want it to be sexually attractive. They want it to be a good parent.
00:36:22.660
They want it to rear its young because that's their ticket to the future. So every one of our
00:36:30.100
own genes cooperates with each, with the other genes in our own genome, all the genes in, in our
00:36:36.280
body cooperate to produce a body because that's their hope for the future. That's the only way
00:36:40.980
they're going to get into the future. And that's what natural selection is all about. Selfish genes
00:36:44.840
are being selected for their capacity to go into the distant future. Now, a virus whose method of
00:36:52.200
getting into the next generation is also via eggs or sperms has the identical interests at heart,
00:37:00.540
so to speak, as your own genes do. And whereas a virus that has a different method of egress from
00:37:07.620
the present body, like being sneezed out and then breathed in by the next one, or coughed out, or
00:37:15.540
coming out as diarrhea and getting into the water supply and getting drunk by the next victim,
00:37:22.240
those viruses or bacteria have not the same interests at heart. They might want the body to
00:37:28.480
stay alive just long enough to get to have the next sneeze. But they're not, if you make a list of
00:37:35.100
all the desiderata, all the things that they want their body to do, it does not include surviving to
00:37:41.460
reproduce. It does not include being sexually attractive. It does not include all the other
00:37:44.940
things I mentioned. But it might include being sexually attractive if the parasite gets passed
00:37:50.500
on by, if it's a sexually transmitted disease. That would be a special case, which kind of proves
00:37:55.400
the rule. So if you were to look at all our own genes, they're just like viruses that have the same
00:38:01.880
interest at heart. And that's what I mean when I say that all our own genes can be thought of
00:38:05.900
as a gigantic colony of viruses, which cooperate with each other because they all have the only
00:38:14.080
one, the only hope of getting into the future is to pass through the same exit route, the same
00:38:19.340
little vessels, which are the sperms or eggs. And so why make a distinction between viruses which
00:38:26.960
get passed on by that route and our own genes? You might as well call them all viruses or call them all
00:38:34.060
genes. That's the sort of sting in the tail in the book anyway.
00:38:38.560
It's a provocative analogy. What is it? Are we aware of any viruses that target the gametes that way?
00:38:45.120
Oh yes. And I think it's something like 8% of what we think of as our genome really did come in.
00:38:52.240
If you'd like to continue listening to this conversation, you'll need to subscribe at
00:38:57.340
samharris.org. Once you do, you'll get access to all full-length episodes of the Making Sense
00:39:02.620
podcast. The podcast is available to everyone through our scholarship program. So if you can't
00:39:07.840
afford a subscription, please request a free account on the website. The Making Sense podcast
00:39:12.860
is ad-free and relies entirely on listener support. And you can subscribe now at samharris.org.
00:39:27.340
for more information on the website. The Making Sense podcast is available to you.