Making Sense of Foundations of Morality | Episode 3 of The Essential Sam Harris
Episode Stats
Words per Minute
157.59941
Summary
The goal of this series is to organize, compile, and juxtapose conversations hosted by Sam Harris into specific areas of interest. This is an ongoing effort to construct a coherent overview of Sam s perspectives and arguments, the various explorations and approaches to the topic, the relevant agreements and disagreements, and the pushbacks and evolving thoughts which his guests have advanced. The purpose of these compilations is not to provide a complete picture of any issue, but to entice you to go deeper into these subjects. Along the way, we ll point you to the full episodes with each featured guest, and at the conclusion, we'll offer some reading, listening, and watching suggestions which range from fun and lighthearted to densely academic. So if you enjoy what we re doing here, please consider becoming a supporter of The Making Sense Podcast. We don t run ads on the podcast, and therefore, therefore, it s made possible entirely through the support of our subscribers. by becoming a member of the podcasting community, you ll benefit entirely from the support made possible by the support you're getting from the membership of the Making Sense Community. You'll hear plenty of crossover into other topics as these dives into the archives unfold, and your thinking about a particular topic may shift as you realize its contingent relationships with others, and so you'll be better able to make sense of the topic. So, get ready to become a member! This is Sam Harris, and you'll get to hear more about what we're doing here. . in this episode of The Essential Sam Harris: Sam Harris What is The Foundations of Morality? - Episode 1: What is Morality, What is it? What does it mean to be a moral good thing? Why is it a good thing ? Why does it matter what we should be good? How can we know what it's a good good thing and what it s good for us to have a good idea of what it means to be good in the world ? What would you like to know about morality? And so on and why it s important to be moral good and moral good, anyway? Can science answer questions of morality How do we know that it s better than we can be better than other things? and so on? We ll find out in the next episode of Making Sense of the Foundations Of Morality The Moral Landscape?
Transcript
00:00:10.880
Just a note to say that if you're hearing this, you are not currently on our subscriber
00:00:14.680
feed and will only be hearing the first part of this conversation.
00:00:18.440
In order to access full episodes of the Making Sense Podcast, you'll need to subscribe at
00:00:24.140
There you'll find our private RSS feed to add to your favorite podcatcher, along with
00:00:30.520
We don't run ads on the podcast, and therefore it's made possible entirely through the support
00:00:35.900
So if you enjoy what we're doing here, please consider becoming one.
00:00:51.480
This is Making Sense of the Foundations of Morality.
00:00:55.440
The goal of this series is to organize, compile, and juxtapose conversations hosted by Sam
00:01:06.480
This is an ongoing effort to construct a coherent overview of Sam's perspectives and arguments,
00:01:12.220
the various explorations and approaches to the topic, the relevant agreements and disagreements,
00:01:18.220
and the pushbacks and evolving thoughts which his guests have advanced.
00:01:21.960
The purpose of these compilations is not to provide a complete picture of any issue, but
00:01:29.060
to entice you to go deeper into these subjects.
00:01:32.480
Along the way, we'll point you to the full episodes with each featured guest, and at the
00:01:37.720
conclusion, we'll offer some reading, listening, and watching suggestions, which range from fun
00:01:47.400
One note to keep in mind for this series, Sam has long argued for a unity of knowledge where
00:01:53.260
the barriers between fields of study are viewed as largely unhelpful artifacts of unnecessarily
00:02:00.660
The pursuit of wisdom and reason in one area of study naturally bleeds into, and greatly
00:02:07.360
You'll hear plenty of crossover into other topics as these dives into the archives unfold.
00:02:14.160
And your thinking about a particular topic may shift as you realize its contingent relationships
00:02:20.840
In this topic, you'll hear the natural overlap with theories of free will, political philosophy,
00:02:33.360
Let's make sense of the foundations of morality.
00:02:36.400
Sam's most important thesis might be the one we'll be exploring in this compilation.
00:02:47.820
It's possibly his most essential argument to grasp in order to understand his positions
00:02:52.420
in the areas of politics, violence, charity, income inequality, and even atheism and religion.
00:03:00.260
He first set the argument down in book form when he wrote The Moral Landscape in 2010.
00:03:05.580
He also delivered a TED Talk, which compressed the argument's central themes into a 15-minute
00:03:13.440
That talk was entitled, Can Science Answer Questions of Morality?
00:03:18.340
Naturally, both the book and the video are recommended to pair with this compilation.
00:03:22.480
As we explore Sam's conversations on this subject from the Making Sense archive, we'll be treading
00:03:30.140
into the exhaustively discussed philosophy of morality.
00:03:33.440
There's an endless taxonomy of positions in this field.
00:03:37.720
The ensuing picture can look like a wildly overgrown and gangly family tree, pointing to countless
00:03:44.140
frameworks with names like consequentialism, utilitarianism, virtue ethics, care ethics, constructivism,
00:03:52.700
nihilism, divine commandment theory, and deontology.
00:03:56.700
But at the base of that tree is a fork that bifurcates the topic fairly sharply.
00:04:03.100
It makes sense for us to start at that primary split and note which limb Sam climbs.
00:04:09.980
Let's label the split with one branch marked as moral realism and the other as its negation,
00:04:18.460
The path of moral realism contends that there are such things as objective moral truths.
00:04:26.120
This would mean that, all things being equal, a declaration like the following is objectively
00:04:33.440
It is morally better to give food to a starving creature than to withhold the food.
00:04:38.980
It would mean that it's possible for moral statements like this to be right or wrong.
00:04:43.620
And to take it even further, it would mean that the truth of this moral statement would
00:04:49.520
remain true even if everyone were wrong and confused about it.
00:04:57.780
Slavery was morally wrong, is not simply a statement of opinion or the suggestion of a
00:05:05.280
Instead, it's a contention that the argument has its foundations outside of culture, personal
00:05:10.660
preference, or historical context, and that slavery was, is, and always will be a moral
00:05:19.100
In philosophical jargon, you could say that objectively true means that it is true from
00:05:28.400
You've likely already gathered that the other branch of the tree, the one labeled moral anti-realism,
00:05:34.960
rejects the entire notion of objective statements in morality.
00:05:38.520
It contends that when it comes to moral statements, we don't have any path to access this so-called
00:05:45.100
view from nowhere, and that moral sentiment is always really a matter of evolved preference,
00:05:51.480
species bias, historical bias, or cultural bias.
00:05:56.300
This branch of ethics declares that the quest for a genuine foundation for our moral sentiments
00:06:01.780
and emotions, that rests outside of our biases, will always result in failure, and that ultimately,
00:06:08.360
all moral sentiments are inescapably subjective, no matter how convincing or widely accepted.
00:06:16.500
Before we go too much further, it's important to note that the outwardly expressed moral attitudes
00:06:22.420
and political positions of realists and anti-realists can strongly cohere.
00:06:28.000
It's entirely possible, even abundantly probable, to find both a realist and an anti-realist arguing
00:06:35.260
that slavery is morally wrong, and to find them both voting for the same political proposition
00:06:43.380
The difference between the two philosophies presents itself when they try to provide their deepest,
00:06:52.120
The realist claims that slavery being wrong is a kind of objective fact, not necessarily
00:06:58.900
exactly like the facts in mathematics or chemistry, but something a bit like them, or at least strongly
00:07:05.180
informed and dictated by those facts, strong enough to be elevated to a factual, moral truth.
00:07:12.300
The moral anti-realist might agree that slavery is a moral wrong, but declare that ultimately,
00:07:18.580
the foundations for that judgment are anthropocentric biases, evolved emotions, historical context,
00:07:25.560
and strong moral instincts, not anything like a scientific fact.
00:07:30.660
One name you'll hear often in this compilation, and in any discussion on this topic, is David Hume.
00:07:37.820
Hume was a brilliant philosopher from Scotland who did his writing in the 1700s.
00:07:42.600
He formulated what has come to be known as the is-ought distinction, which argued that you can't get an
00:07:49.800
ought from an is. Or, to reword it in philosophical hypothesis form, Hume argued that there is no
00:07:57.880
description of the way the universe is, which tells us how the universe ought to be.
00:08:02.760
This insight is what really fertilizes the entire branch of anti-realism in the field of ethics.
00:08:10.280
You may have already guessed that Sam very confidently moves down the moral realism branch.
00:08:16.720
And while he conceptually agrees with Hume's logic, he considers the confusion that it's caused,
00:08:22.820
and its resulting moral subjectivism and cultural relativism, to be a kind of ethical and political
00:08:28.660
emergency. Sam asserts that Hume's is-ought insight has led many people to conclude that science
00:08:35.620
really has nothing to say about morality. The relativist argument suggests that because science
00:08:41.460
pursues the is-side of Hume's distinction, and morality pursues the ought-side, questions of morality
00:08:48.420
are completely divorced from science and are purely subjective matters for which there is no objective
00:08:54.200
arbiter. Sam points out that this attitude has rendered many otherwise moral and intelligent
00:09:00.800
people mute and blind when it comes to casting judgment on the moral behaviors of others, and
00:09:06.840
especially other cultures. Sam's approach to objective morality allows him to escape this moral paralysis,
00:09:14.900
and, as you can imagine, his resulting utterances have landed him in hot water from time to time.
00:09:20.440
Before we get to our first clip, it's also important to clear something up about Sam's brand of moral
00:09:27.300
realism early so we can avoid a common misperception. Sam's argument in favor of moral realism does not
00:09:35.620
imply that there is only one correct answer to a moral question. It also does not imply that he knows the
00:09:42.120
right answer. It's only a contention that there are such right answers, or, more accurately, that there are
00:09:49.200
right directions to move towards, that it's possible to objectively compare the moral value of two
00:09:56.100
states of being and two states of the universe, and that it is possible to have real, objective
00:10:02.220
confidence in those moral assessments, and that it's therefore possible to make genuine moral progress.
00:10:09.440
But, and this is the very delicate part, it is entirely possible that one must move away from that right
00:10:18.220
direction in order to navigate towards a higher peak of moral states. This is the wrinkle that starts to
00:10:24.240
paint his moral landscape as a kind of mountain hiking adventure, with endless peaks and valleys, foggy
00:10:30.600
hilltops, dangerous caverns, canyons, wrong turns, impassable swamps, and open upward clearings.
00:10:39.440
What Sam argues is that morality, when properly understood, is a navigation problem which requires
00:10:45.980
ever-improving methods to draw better maps, manufacture accurate compasses, and devise a
00:10:52.360
good pair of binoculars so that we can have confidence that we are climbing to higher and
00:10:56.540
higher ground. So, when we brought up our first example to show the split between moral realists
00:11:04.740
and anti-realists, the idea that feeding a starving creature rather than depriving it,
00:11:10.800
we added a tiny four-word phrase in passing to qualify it, all things being equal. But the funny
00:11:18.520
thing about our actual lives and real-world situations is that all things are almost never
00:11:24.220
equal. In an actual situation you might encounter in the world, the food in question may be your last
00:11:30.720
bites, and you'll starve to death if you feed the creature. Or there may be several starving creatures
00:11:36.340
in front of you, and you only have enough food for one of them. Or maybe this creature will devour
00:11:41.880
two other healthy creatures if you feed it. Adding wrinkles like this and playing with all of these
00:11:47.660
crazy variables tends to make things unequal and morally complex. But, in an effort to distill and
00:11:55.080
expound upon different moral frameworks and discover psychological and philosophical insights,
00:12:01.000
philosophers and writers have been conjuring up fun and sometimes diabolical thought experiments in
00:12:06.560
situations like this to try to flatten or equalize certain elements and isolate others.
00:12:13.200
We'll be hearing some fun thought experiments, and some not-so-fun ones, throughout this compilation.
00:12:18.340
So, let's get to our first clip and introduce a famous thought experiment that we'll be returning
00:12:24.360
to frequently. The clip is a conversation with Australian philosopher Peter Singer, who at this
00:12:30.740
point seems to have the descriptor of world's most influential living philosopher as a permanent
00:12:36.260
addendum to his name. We'll begin with what has become a famous simple thought experiment that
00:12:42.460
Singer used in 1971 in Philosophy and Public Affairs, an academic journal that was little
00:12:49.060
known at the time. The thought experiment goes like this.
00:12:55.300
Imagine you have just purchased a nice pair of new shoes, and you're walking by a pond.
00:13:00.820
You know this pond well, and you know its depth and probable dangers. It's very shallow. It only comes
00:13:06.720
up to your waist. Suddenly, you see a small child in the pond flailing for her life and struggling.
00:13:15.120
She's clearly in distress and in imminent danger of drowning.
00:13:19.200
Do you run into the pond and rescue her, knowing that you will muddy your shoes and certainly ruin them?
00:13:26.640
If you're waiting for a more complicated or challenging choice, it's not coming.
00:13:31.760
That's the whole story, and that's the whole thought experiment.
00:13:37.760
Of course I run into the pond. Who cares about the shoes?
00:13:42.000
Now, Singer takes that answer and suggests that we,
00:13:45.480
and he's speaking mostly about those of us in the affluent world,
00:13:49.440
that we are all the time in a very similar moral position as the pedestrian walking by the pond.
00:13:58.840
And let's also say you already had a pair of perfectly usable shoes at home.
00:14:05.760
Go back to the moment when you were at the shoe store and looking at them on display.
00:14:10.820
What if, instead of making that purchase, you knew that you could donate that $90 to a charity
00:14:16.220
which had displayed solid data that it could use that money, with a very high degree of probability,
00:14:21.600
to save the life of a child in Eritrea who would otherwise soon die?
00:14:26.100
Is choosing to purchase the shoes anyway a choice that is morally equivalent
00:14:31.160
to strolling past the drowning child and keeping your new shoes shiny and clean
00:14:37.800
This arresting question has spawned a swarm of responses, supportive movements, clever challenges,
00:14:47.880
creative edits, defeated frustrations, and counter-considerations.
00:14:52.760
We'll be playing with Singer's shallow pond a good bit throughout this compilation
00:14:56.880
to flesh out Sam's take on it and his particular run at the eternally vexing problem of morality.
00:15:04.540
An obvious distinction to draw between the moment at the pond versus the moment at the shoe store
00:15:09.400
is something like an act of omission versus an act of commission.
00:15:14.640
In other words, is there a difference between failing to act and choosing to act
00:15:21.460
Let's jump into the first clip, where Sam is speaking with Peter Singer in episode 48.
00:15:31.420
Is there an important moral distinction between acts of omission and acts of commission?
00:15:40.300
So how does, and your famous shallow pond example put some pressure on this here.
00:15:46.700
So how do you think about the difference between not saving a life that would be very easy for you to save
00:15:56.160
And this obviously also relates to end-of-life considerations of the sort you mentioned,
00:16:00.640
the difference we seem to hold on to between removing life support
00:16:05.340
and passively letting someone die versus actively killing them,
00:16:09.300
which in many cases might be the more merciful thing to do.
00:16:12.540
Yeah, so my view is that the distinction between killing and letting die
00:16:19.000
or between acts and omissions, it's put in different ways,
00:16:28.200
It may be a marker for other things of more significance,
00:16:31.740
like it may be a marker for motives, for instance.
00:16:35.180
So if somebody were to say to me, suppose I say, look, you should give to this effective charity.
00:16:44.420
You should give to the Against Malaria Foundation because it will distribute bed nets
00:16:48.300
in places where there's a lot of malaria and where children die from malaria.
00:16:53.180
And if you donate what I know you can afford to donate to the Against Malaria Foundation,
00:16:58.440
they will use it to distribute bed nets and you will be saving at least one child's life.
00:17:04.480
That is a real organization and a real example.
00:17:07.340
And let's say the person doesn't do that, right?
00:17:10.020
So then that person has, in one sense, let a child die.
00:17:13.420
Do I think of that person exactly the same as somebody who traveled to Africa,
00:17:18.700
shot a small child and then traveled back to the United States?
00:17:22.500
I know that there's a huge psychological difference in that person that many of us are apathetic
00:17:31.860
or don't care enough, don't feel psychologically drawn to help people who we can't even see.
00:17:40.280
But for someone to actually have the malice and the will to travel, to find a child,
00:17:46.160
to kill that child, has to be a completely horrible, depraved person.
00:17:51.380
So sometimes the distinction between acts and omissions will signal something like that.
00:17:56.880
Why did this person go out of their way to kill?
00:17:59.460
Whereas in the other case, they simply didn't do enough to save a life.
00:18:04.260
But then let's look at another case, the medical case that you mentioned.
00:18:09.260
So an infant has been born prematurely and has had a very severe bleeding in the brain,
00:18:20.540
They find that all of the parts of the brain that are associated with consciousness,
00:18:26.440
like the cortex, have been irreversibly destroyed.
00:18:30.440
Now, there's two possible things that might happen in these circumstances.
00:18:36.720
One might be that the doctors, after discussion with the parents, say,
00:18:44.600
They'll survive if we continue to treat them, but they'll just lie in bed all day and never
00:18:50.860
be able to communicate with anyone, probably never have any conscious experiences at all,
00:18:58.100
And the doctors will then say, and the parents will usually agree, so we could withdraw the
00:19:06.960
We can withdraw the respirator and your baby will die.
00:19:09.780
And parents will typically say, if you think that's best, doctor, then I'm okay with that.
00:19:16.240
Now, that is seen as a letting die, as an allowing to die, not as a killing.
00:19:21.760
On the other hand, it might have happened that because it took some time to carry out the
00:19:27.300
diagnosis, because the baby was particularly vigorous and so on, that the baby no longer needs
00:19:36.880
The baby is never going to communicate in any way, probably never going to be conscious.
00:19:40.660
She's going to have to be fed through a tube and lie in a bed.
00:19:42.960
But you can't bring about the baby's death by withdrawing the respirator.
00:19:48.060
And let's just say that there's nothing else you can do that will bring about the baby's
00:19:51.700
The baby is otherwise, apart from this massive and irreparable brain damage, the baby is
00:19:57.660
Now, I think that if you're prepared to say that it was justifiable to withdraw the respirator,
00:20:04.380
you ought to be prepared to say it would be justifiable to give the baby a lethal injection
00:20:12.520
In both cases, you know exactly what the consequences of your action will be.
00:20:16.620
In both cases, your intention is to bring about the death of the child.
00:20:21.240
Your motivation is equally, I would say, equally good, equally reasonable in both cases.
00:20:33.020
But legally, of course, one is murder and the other is, well, maybe it's slightly gray in
00:20:40.820
But anyway, it's done in every neonatal intensive care unit in every major city in the United
00:20:54.040
But that's, as I say, that's a case where I would think we ought to be able to accept
00:21:01.020
active steps on the basis of saying it's no different from the other case.
00:21:06.200
And certainly there are cases where the active step is the one that bypasses an immense amount
00:21:15.140
In other cases where there is some consciousness, not exactly the case I described, but there
00:21:19.580
is some consciousness, I do know of cases where people will say, you know, no, we can't
00:21:26.500
But if the baby gets pneumonia, we won't give antibiotics.
00:21:30.820
And so then the baby will suffer a lingering death from pneumonia over days or maybe even
00:21:37.480
a couple of weeks, you know, which is a horrible thing and a pointless thing to do if you decided
00:21:47.040
I want to go back to the issue of the shallow pond.
00:21:52.180
It would take a very different sort of person to go to Africa with the intention of killing
00:21:57.040
someone than merely decline to buy a bed net when told on good information that this would
00:22:08.320
But I think you're saying that it's natural for us to view them as different.
00:22:12.200
And because it requires actually a different psychology to do one versus the other, they
00:22:19.820
But if we abstract away from those differences and talk about public policies and what governments
00:22:25.800
should do, then the act and omission difference shouldn't be morally salient to us anymore.
00:22:35.400
I'm not going to say that it shouldn't be at all morally salient because there are questions
00:22:39.020
in what governments do in terms of the examples that they set.
00:22:43.360
But I do think it's very serious that governments allow people to die when they could prevent
00:22:47.900
them, when they have the resources to prevent them.
00:22:51.060
And so I certainly think that the governments of the wealthier nations of the world should
00:22:57.400
be getting together and developing policies to eliminate preventable child deaths and preventable
00:23:06.600
They did make a reasonable effort in terms of the Millennium Development Goals to reduce
00:23:14.640
The number of children dying fell quite significantly during that period, as did the number of people
00:23:23.800
But I'm concerned whether sufficient progress is continuing to be made.
00:23:29.760
I think more progress could have been made even in that period, although some progress was
00:23:37.400
And that applies to governments, but it also applies to individuals.
00:23:41.140
I think all of us who can afford to donate to effective charities ought to be doing that
00:23:52.300
How do you view the ethical significance of proximity, if there is any?
00:23:57.640
I mean, obviously, there's an immense psychological significance that the starving person on my
00:24:02.140
doorstep is different, certainly more salient than the starving person in a distant country
00:24:08.040
whose existence I know about, at least in the abstract.
00:24:11.480
Presumably, you think that that difference is far bigger than it should be.
00:24:17.460
But is there any ethical significance to proximity, the problem in your backyard as opposed to the
00:24:26.160
Well, I'd say not to proximity in itself, again.
00:24:30.060
We can perhaps be more confident about what we're achieving when things are in our backyard
00:24:36.800
We can talk to the people who are affected by it.
00:24:38.700
But we do have very good research now about effective non-profit organizations that are
00:24:47.960
So there's organizations like GiveWell that do research on effective charities.
00:24:53.680
There's an organization I founded called The Life You Can Save, and it has a website which
00:25:00.480
lists charities that we've vetted, and some of it draws on GiveWell's research, some of it
00:25:10.940
And if you can have a high level of confidence in the effectiveness of what you're doing,
00:25:19.380
As you correctly said, it is very different psychologically.
00:25:22.760
But morally, it's not very different from things that are going on in your backyard.
00:25:28.040
Given that it is so different psychologically, I mean, presumably, if I told you that there's
00:25:32.860
a starving person by my front door today that I just stepped over on the way to this podcast
00:25:37.900
because I was, you know, I'm busy, you would view me with something close to horror and repugnance
00:25:46.200
But if I told you that I got yet another appeal from a good charity, which I didn't act on, you
00:25:54.880
would just view me as a more or less psychologically normal, if somewhat aloof person.
00:26:01.320
Do you view our moral progress personally and collectively as a matter of collapsing that
00:26:08.760
distance as much as psychologically possible so that we really can't put distant suffering
00:26:16.180
Yes, I do think that's an indicator of progress.
00:26:19.600
And it's, you know, the psychology is understandable, of course.
00:26:23.180
Our ancestors for millennia, for perhaps hundreds of thousands of years, if we go back even,
00:26:29.900
could go back even to social primates before there were humans at all, these ancestors lived
00:26:36.320
in small social groups, face-to-face groups where they knew people and they would help others
00:26:42.580
and cooperate with them in various ways, but they had no relations perhaps even to people
00:26:47.460
who lived across the mountain range in the next valley.
00:26:51.800
And now suddenly, suddenly in terms of evolutionary time anyway, we live in a world where we have
00:26:57.560
instant communications, where we have very rapid delivery of assistance, where we have good
00:27:03.600
ways of working out what is going to help people most effectively.
00:27:07.800
And our psychology has not changed rapidly enough to cope with this.
00:27:18.560
There's an interesting note about Singer's pond analogy and the idea that Sam raised about
00:27:23.780
evaluating the kind of person who would stroll by a child drowning in a pond versus the kind
00:27:31.860
Singer originally wrote the pond story in an essay about a mass humanitarian crisis in East
00:27:38.780
Bengal in 1971, spurred on by a civil war and a devastating cyclone.
00:27:44.820
He presented the pond to argue for the presence of a moral opportunity, and perhaps for a moral
00:27:50.080
obligation, of wealthy countries to intervene with food, shelter, and rescue.
00:27:55.800
We can map that same character analysis that Sam suggested onto the national level and ask,
00:28:01.860
what kind of country declines to feasibly rescue those in a foreign crisis versus what kind
00:28:08.340
of country declines to offer generic foreign aid absent any acute humanitarian crisis?
00:28:14.820
A screaming child drowning in a pond is an emergency, but the slow drip of individual preventable
00:28:21.360
deaths from hunger, illness, and poverty, and spread across entire continents does not seem
00:28:27.780
to present itself in that way, or to expose the kind of people we are.
00:28:34.260
What if we gathered all of those individuals into one location, like a sports stadium, and
00:28:39.500
announced that a bomb would kill them all at midnight unless we easily diffused it?
00:28:44.360
That edit sounds extreme, but it only gathers the location of these preventable deaths to the
00:28:50.300
same venue, and it makes explicit the imminence of their demise.
00:28:54.000
Somehow that makes it feel more like a newsworthy emergency that only a moral monster would ignore.
00:29:01.060
But again, Singer argues that this may actually be the situation that most of us are in today,
00:29:09.980
This is the deeply challenging work that the pond analogy does.
00:29:13.660
So, let's stay with that last thread from Sam and Singer's conversation of proximity,
00:29:20.220
and the tension between psychology and moral philosophy.
00:29:24.660
Like all moral dilemmas and thought experiments, you can start to tinker with the variables in
00:29:29.820
certain ways that are designed to highlight how your moral intuitions might shift with each
00:29:37.940
But this time, you see five children drowning instead of one.
00:29:44.160
They're all at different distances from you, spread throughout the pond.
00:29:48.500
You're quite certain that in the time it will take you to reach and rescue one of them,
00:29:56.940
Assuming you're still willing to ruin your shoes.
00:30:00.720
Maybe you decide that flipping a coin is the best method.
00:30:04.000
But what if one of the children happens to be your child?
00:30:09.700
Waiting past the cries for help from an unfortunate, unknown child?
00:30:14.460
How about if you knew all of the struggling children,
00:30:17.140
and you know that one of them has a terminal illness,
00:30:24.980
What if one of the children is known to be showing signs of being a scientific prodigy,
00:30:31.860
and she's likely to be a great benefit to humanity?
00:30:34.260
What if you think all of these factors are just too vulgar,
00:30:39.200
and you simply go to whichever one happens to draw you first while you close your eyes?
00:30:44.140
Would that method favor the child who happens to yell the loudest?
00:30:48.320
If we keep our eyes open and just follow our instinct,
00:30:51.840
would we inevitably end up being drawn towards the child who's the cutest?
00:30:55.320
Or even the child who looks a little like us and reminds us of our kin?
00:31:00.100
We can keep playing these kinds of games forever.
00:31:03.340
We could even make it nearly identical to the famous trolley problem,
00:31:07.240
the thought experiment which ties five people to a railroad track,
00:31:11.140
while one person is fastened to a separate track.
00:31:16.880
you're given the choice to divert an out-of-control trolley towards the one,
00:31:24.320
In our pond, we can imagine that four of the children are clinging to a rapidly deflating life raft,
00:31:30.420
and they could all grab hold of it and be dragged to safety by you,
00:31:33.740
while one isolated child is drowning by himself a hundred feet away.
00:31:37.480
Is there a right choice for problems like these?
00:31:42.040
We're going to go to our second clip to focus on the suggestion
00:31:44.940
that there are right answers to these questions.
00:31:48.500
This guest will argue that our intuitions lead us to actions
00:31:51.920
that are compromised by our evolved psychological biases
00:31:55.260
to favor creatures with which we can empathize.
00:32:01.620
it's certainly easier to empathize with someone who's close enough
00:32:09.440
rather than a distant, nameless, faceless, voiceless child.
00:32:14.200
We know that it's also easier to empathize with a single child
00:32:19.340
over a huge number of distant, nameless children
00:32:24.600
In fact, as you'll hear Sam and this next guest point out,
00:32:28.420
this specific aspect of our psychology is even more curious,
00:32:32.480
where our ability to empathize with a specific starving child
00:32:35.760
is reduced when you simply place the same child
00:32:39.040
amongst the company of thousands of others just like him.
00:32:45.940
a professor of psychology formerly of Yale University
00:32:52.380
Bloom has had several wonderful conversations with Sam,
00:32:56.600
which came just after the release of Bloom's book
00:33:02.240
In it, he argues that our much-ballyhooed capacity for empathy
00:33:12.400
In fact, it may often be more of a bug than a feature
00:33:33.020
which is that empathy, in many cases, is harmful
00:33:43.720
So tell me about what you've said about empathy
00:33:49.560
with the most boring way ever to begin anything,
00:33:57.320
and I think my position is easily misunderstood.
00:34:13.620
I mean, I want to make the world a better place.
00:34:15.960
Other people use the term empathy very narrowly
00:34:24.400
understanding what they think and what they feel.
00:34:31.820
I think very great and wonderful and kind people
00:34:45.180
one reason why bullies are very good at being bullies
00:34:59.460
from the other form that you're about to describe
00:35:05.020
When we talk about psychopaths being devoid of empathy,
00:35:13.300
That is not something that prototypically evil people lack.
00:35:24.740
So, you know, another term for cognitive empathy
00:35:38.080
But in the hands of somebody with malevolent ends,
00:35:40.460
intelligence could be used to make them a lot worse.
00:35:50.320
is a tool that could be used any way you want it.
00:35:53.100
And the very best people in the world have tons of it.
00:36:01.680
and this actually matches what most psychologists
00:36:11.380
and David Hume and other philosophers call sympathy.
00:36:14.800
And what it refers to is feeling what other people feel.
00:36:31.980
And you could see why people are such fans of this.
00:36:37.320
It dissolves the boundaries between me and you.
00:36:40.200
And there's a lot of psychological research showing
00:36:46.740
Dan Batson has done some wonderful studies on them,
00:36:55.020
but the main problem is it serves as a spotlight.
00:36:57.880
It zooms me in on a person in the here and now.
00:37:13.260
that governments and societies care so much more
00:37:35.460
are a tiny proportion of gun homicides in America,
00:37:57.200
and make all the mass shootings go away forever,
00:38:01.360
nobody would know based on the homicide numbers.
00:38:10.920
It causes us to freak out at the suffering of one